Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2022, Commentary
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) was born in Stuttgart, Germany in 1770. He became the outstanding German philosopher of his day and was renowned throughout Europe. His major works, The Philosophy of Right and The Philosophy of History, contain the most important elements of his political philosophy. Hegel was an absolute Idealist. His most famous quote, "the rational is actual and the actual is rational," is the basis for his position. Bed-rocked on this, the writer conceptualized Hegel's idea of individual freedom and the absolute power of the state on individuals.
The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 2001
Political Science, XXXVIII, (1986) pp. 99 112
OGIRISI: a New Journal of African Studies, 2017
The need for reconciliation of individualism and communitarianism in search for an ideal state has been the main preoccupation of social and political philosophers. Unlike other philosophers like Hobbes and Locke that view the individual and the state as being incompatible and therefore seek to achieve some sort of compromise between the two principles, Hegel believes that the individual and the state are mutually independent. For him, individual freedom understood as rational freedom is achieved through the rational institutions of the state. Thus, the state's institutions must harmonise truly the collective interest with the objective good of individuals. The will of the state, the universal will is the good; it is the realisation of freedom and so is unquestionable. This paper discusses how Hegel reconciles individual freedom with the authority of the state. Besides, it argues that the absolutism of the Hegel's state tends to restrict individual right and freedom which, in Hegel's view, must be actualised in the state. Finally, this paper contends that Hegel's reduction of freedom to rationality tends to encourage indiscriminate utilisation of human reason to create things that can erode human dignity and values. It suggests that the recognition of the place of God in human thought and life would make life meaningful and valuable.
Eastern Review
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel was one of the philosophic giants of the nineteenth century. Well versed in both ancient and more recent philosophical tracts, he rejected the individualism of Hobbes and Locke, as well as their notion that the state was an agency set up in the first place to protect life and property, and, drawing inspiration from Aristotle, outlined a vision of the state as an agency bound, in the first place, to protect the weak and the powerless. Hegel further rejected Kant’s individualistic ethics and counseled that ethical behavior had to be understood as taking place in a social context, with real duties toward other people. For Hegel, an individual had rights and duties within the context of the family, in the community, and, as a citizen, vis-à-vis the state. He emphasized the network of duties in which each individual finds himself, urging political moderation and concern for the good of the entire community. He has been condemned as a proto-totalitarian, laud...
Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, 2010
This fresh and original book argues that the central questions in Hegel's practical philosophy are the central questions in modern accounts of freedom: What is freedom, or what would it be to act freely? Is it possible so to act? And how important is leading a free life? Robert Pippin argues that the core of Hegel's answers is a social theory of agency, the view that agency is not exclusively a matter of the self-relation and self-determination of an individual but requires the right sort of engagement with, and recognition by, others. Using a detailed analysis of key Hegelian texts, Pippin develops this interpretation to reveal the bearing of Hegel's claims on many contemporary issues, including much-discussed core problems in the liberal democratic tradition. His important study will be valuable for all readers who are interested in Hegel's philosophy and in the modern problems of agency and freedom.
Philosophy in Review, Vol 34, No 1-2 (2014)
Philosophy Compass, 2007
Hegel's theory of freedom is complex and sweeping, and while most interpreters of Hegel will readily agree that it is the centerpiece of his political philosophy, perhaps also of his social philosophy and philosophy of history, they will just as readily disagree about what exactly the theory claims. Such interpretive disagreements have fueled, in large part, the resurgence of interest in Hegelian philosophy over the last few decades.
Hegel's Thought in Europe Currents, Crosscurrents and Undercurrents, Lisa Herzog (Ed.), Palgrave, 2013, 2013
In the works of Kant (1724–1804), Fichte (1762–1814), and Hegel, German idealism effected a philosophical revolution in its new conceptions of reason, and of reason’s practical role in legislating for morality and politics. The central tenet of Hegel’s idealism is the unity of thought and being, a processual unity secured by the historical realization of reason in the world. Hegel’s philosophy provided a self-conscious comprehension of this unity and its expressions in existence. In his Philosophy of Right (1820–1821), Hegel had asserted that the real is rational, and the rational is real;1 but this is a speculative claim, affirming both identity and non-identity. Its ambiguity had serious exegetical consequences for Hegel’s students and followers. The reality or effectiveness of reason could be understood to signify an ongoing historical process, still burdened with contradictions and insufficiencies that must be purged away in the course of further development. Alternatively, Hegel’s claim might appear to confer rational legitimacy on the existing political and social order. The question is the extent to which the prevailing forms of religion, politics and society satisfy the demands of reason and freedom, and how are these standards themselves to be understood and defended? The Hegelian heritage split in response to these questions.
According to Hegel, the development of consciousness is determined by God the absolute and the process of development must be rational and necessary, which provides little room for individual's freedom. However, like other philosophers, due to the consideration on the problem of retribution of ethical responsibility to individuals, Hegel tries to argue that individual's freedom is still compatible with his deterministic philosophy of history. However, based upon Kosch's interpretation of Kierkegaard's two senses of freedom, this paper argue that under Hegel's philosophy of history freedom is impossible. For under Hegel's philosophy he must deny the individual's freedom as capacity to form intentions that are independent from determination by prior events (including mental states), and therefore individuals cannot posit choices on their own. However, without the ability to posit choices, individuals cannot have real freedom. Therefore individual's freedom is incompatible with Hegel's philosophy of history. If we think individual's freedom really exist, than we must reject Hegel's philosophy. This paper only argues that the Hegel's philosophy must imply there is no individual freedom, instead of proving the existence of individual's freedom or denying the system of Hegel's philosophy.
REASON AND STATE FROM THE PERSPECTIVE OF WILHELM FRIEDRICH HEGEL (Atena Editora), 2024
With this article we intend to demonstrate the relationship between the State and Reason in the view of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel. To do this, we will address the Hegelian conception of the State and the interaction of this institution with the individual and civil society. Added to this, we will try to observe how the State, interpreted by Hegel, adjusts to the particular aspects of each nation and, especially, to the rationality that it incorporates. We will deal with Hegel's conception of the individual and his existence within a rational State and how individual freedoms are recognized and manifested (that is, the role of the individual in this institution, including the rights and duties of the citizen). This study is essentially bibliographic and, for this, we focus on his relevant Hegelian works Philosophy of History (1999) and Hegel's Principles of the Philosophy of Law (1997).
History of Political Thought, 2024
Hegel saw freedom not primarily as a property of the individual’s will, but of a totality (from which individual freedom is metaphysically derived). This aspect of Hegel’s political theory stemmed from his attempt to construct a state that could foster a renewal of Christian spirituality. This project had to confront the fragmentation of the Holy Roman Empire, which Hegel attributed to the self-interestedness of its component parts. This historical case for the priority of the whole over its parts, however, was soon supplanted by a philosophical argument for a political totality whose freedom entailed its subordination of conflicting parts within itself.
Contemporary Philosophy. A New Survey. Vol. 12. Philosophy of Justice, 2015
For Hegel, right is inextricably tied to free will, which he sees as an expression of spirit. His Philosophy of Right 1 locates the foundation of right exactly in freedom and spirit. Many have viewed this coupling of right and freedom with spirit as problematic. Hegel has for a long time -at least since Isaiah Berlin's "Two Concepts of Liberty" -been interpreted as a representative of positive freedom (being directed by a "true self") and linked to a totalitarian idea of the state. Recent contributions have to a large extent freed Hegel from such charges, focusing on how the freedom of the individual is not only compatible with participation in society, but also realized through it. 2 The state is not understood as the "march" of some god external to human history. 3 Terry Pinkard's recent Hegel's Naturalism is an example of such a view: "Spirit" is not an independent, supersensible being directing history from the beyond, 4 but is the collective and individual agency of self-interpreting organisms. 5 Axel Honneth goes further in his Das Recht der Freiheit, a reconstruction of Hegel's Philosophy of Right in a way suitable for the contemporary mind: Honneth throws the idealist, monist concept of spirit completely overboard. 6 Why was Hegel so concerned with spirit and why are we so concerned with distancing ourselves from it?
2012
The introduction ( § §1-33) to Hegel's Philosophy of Right is the key to the work's structure, its argumentative strategy and it functions as a foundation for Hegel's practical philosophy in general. Its explanatory potential is best realised by situating it within the systematic context of the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences and the Science of Logic. This interpretative strategy reveals that for Hegel, the true site of agency is 'the concept' and that particular individuals and their arbitrary activity are at best the concept's 'appearance'. This does not render their activity 'false' but describes how willing and freedom are 'for us' as self-conscious subjects that confront an external world. For Hegel, 'true' freedom in the sense of 'self-determination to itself' resides with the universal and singular concept that negatively unites itself with its objectivity to form what he calls the 'Idea of the will' or 'right'. This interpretation contradicts the mainstream of contemporary Hegel scholarship since its proponents either deny the reality of the universal concept as agent or absolutely differentiate between the concept's activity (subjective action) and its objective reality (norms, institutions). This prevents the interpreter from appreciating that it is Hegel's concept that is manifest in form of particular willing subjects and their socio-political context. Since most commentators associate 'activity' or 'freedom' primarily with particular subjects, their notions of freedom are, by Hegel's standards, either empty and fail to describe actual willing or they fall short of the standard of 'true freedom', viz. 'self-determination to itself' because their agents' freedom depends on something that differs from the agents. 1 The present commentary argues that such a dilemma can be avoided by an interpretation that attributes agency to Hegel's concept. By determining itself to be Idea, the universal concept determines itself (as subject) to itself (as object) and rational agency and rational institutions are grasped as aspects of the same entity. This is what Hegel calls the unconditioned Idea of right or 'objective freedom'.
Hegel Bulletin, 2015
Hegel’s Philosophy of Right responds to two dichotomies. One is between the freedom of rational thought in its practical application and the givenness of natural impulses and desires. Against Kant Hegel argues that pure reason alone cannot determine the content of any maxim or principle of action. Thus Hegel must find a way in which the content of natural needs and impulses – the only source of content for maxims of action – can be transfigured into contents of rationally self-given principles and maxims. Hegel also responds to the dichotomy between the individual agent and the social whole within which agents act. Hegel argues that this dichotomy is specious because human beings are fundamentally social practitioners and because neither social practices nor individual agents have priority over the other. There are no social practices without social practitioners and there are no social practitioners without social practices. Hegel’s response to this second dichotomy allows him to respond to the first one as well. The elaboration and specialization of natural needs and desires through exchange relations and the social division of labor transfigures the contents of those needs and desires into collectively self-given ends. The social practices producing this transfiguration and meeting these ends form the contents of implicit principles of right. These implicit principles are collectively self-given because they result from the social practices collectively developed to meet these needs. Only acts that are executed and accepted by an agent are free acts. This strong condition requires that an agent’s intentions correspond to the actual nature and consequences of his or her act. Since the aims, the principles, and the means of action are fundamentally social, these strong constraints entail that free action is possible only within a community which makes known its structure and the role of its members within it and their contribution to it, so that its members can act on the basis of that knowledge. Hegel’s theory of the state is a theory of a communal structure that makes such explicit, free action possible. In briefest compass, Hegel holds that laws are legitimate only insofar as they codify those practices that have been developed in order to achieve human freedom, and laws are obligatory only insofar as they are necessary for achieving human freedom. Hegel’s government is designed to codify and promulgate such laws. Hegel’s legislature is designed to make known to the citizens at large, through their corporate representatives, that laws have such a basis and how individual roles and actions fit within the community as a whole.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.