Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review 50/2 (2011): 347–65
The paper argues that applications of the principle that “ought” implies “can” (OIC) depend on normative considerations even if the link between “ought” and “can” is logical in nature. Thus, we should reject a common, “factualist” conception of OIC and endorse weak “normativism”. Even if we use OIC as the rule ““cannot” therefore “not ought””, applying OIC is not a mere matter of facts and logic, as factualists claim, but often draws on “proto-ideals” of moral agency.
Prometheus - Journal of Philosophy
Brito (2010) proposes a naturalistic analysis of morality, disagreeing with some authors who postulate an insurmountable is-ought gap. Here, we present his main arguments and advance some criticisms to them. Brito’s strategy consists in grounding the normative notion of ought on volitive notions, like “will” and “want”. In his perspective, to reach the moral level, a will has to be directed to itself and to all other wills. We try to show that this strategy fails, since moral normativity cannot be grounded on subjective phenomena, regardless of the contents of these phenomena. We also show some incoherence in Brito’s ideias about the possibility of is-ought reduction, as he seems to advocate that it is not possible to reduce “ought” to “is” while he also proposes the reduction of oughts to facts about volition.
Philosophia, 1989
The purpose of this paper is to discuss whether moral requirements range over actions or attempts. In particular, I shall examine two contexts in ethics theory that some have thought provide a basis for believing that attempts are what are morally required of agents. In both of these contexts there is an implicit appeal to the principle that 'ought' implies 'can'. In order to set the stage for my discussion of the central question, therefore, I need to begin by explaining how I think appeals to the principle that 'ought' implies 'can' typically work. Article: Part 1 If an agent is charged with wrongdoing, there are several ways that he might defend himself. He might, for example, admit that he has done something wrong, but contend that he should not be blamed for doing so. An agent who makes this defense is said to be offering an excuse for his behaviour. That one acted under duress is an example of an excuse. If I am rude to you after having been up all night tending to my sick mother. I will admit that I have behaved improperly but claim that because of the circumstances, I ought not to be blamed.
According normativism about meaning, an expression’s meaning has normative implications for how speakers ought or ought not to, how they may and how the mustn’t use it. However, some authors – notably Katrin Glüer, Peter Pagin, Asa Wikforss and Anandi Hattiangadi – contest the normativist claim. They do agree that the rules constituting an expression’s meaning establish a standard of correctness that sorts uses of the expression into correct and incorrect ones, and they agree that it is precisely this what distinguishes meaningful expressions from mere noises. But they insist that the obtaining of such a standard is a purely descriptive matter. I try to bring out why this is mistaken by making use of a distinction between two ways of understanding constitutive rules, introduced by John Haugeland, and by showing how these embody two irreconcilable perspectives on linguistic practice, which the anti-normativists run together.
The paper aims at formulating a certain trilemma that applies to justifying moral norms. The trilemma can be succinctly stated as follows: any attempt to derive a “moral-ought statement” from an “is-statement” with a justificatory goal (i.e. to justify the “moral-ought statement”), even if it were successful in its “derivation” part (i.e. logically correct), would be unsuccessful in its “justificatory” part for one of the following three reasons: (1) it would consider each human action of which a factual statement can be made as morally obligatory, thus “justifying” a large number of implausible moral norms; or (2) it would presuppose a moral norm not derivable from facts; or (3) it would not explain why the distinction – made based on extra-moral criteria – between those factual statements about human actions from which moral norms can be derived and those from which they cannot be derived should count as morally relevant. The trilemma is illustrated in the paper by an analysis of Searle’s well-known attempt at deriving “ought” from “is”. Some further implications of the trilemma regarding the proper way of justifying moral norms are also examined.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy
In this paper, I develop a standard-relational theory of ‘ought’ and a nonHumean theory of reasons (oughtism). Together, they explain why ‘A ought to X’ entails not only that there are reasons for A to X, but also that the balance of reasons favours X-ing. The latter explanation depends on a theory of weight, in which the weight of a reason depends on the position of a rule (standard) in an order of priorities. The theories are truth conditional, but do not require objective normative facts for the truth of ‘ought’ judgments and judgments about reasons.
Journal of business systems, governance and ethics, 2006
According to Hilary Putnam, the 'moral is clear: when we are dealing with any important value disagreement, we assume facts are irrelevant at our peril. No convincing logical reason can be given for the logical irrelevance of fact to value judgements, even if we accept the positivist conception of what a "fact" is.' (2002, p. 78) This paper explores why the dichotomies engendered by the 'positivist' approach fact/value, positive/normative and descriptive/evaluativeare false. The main reason, the paper argues, is that the fundamental principle underlying the approach fails. This principle, the 'no ought from is argument' (or the NOFIA), is the formally structured argument that a value (ought) cannot logically be derived from a fact (is). The paper rejects the NOFIA and, especially, its iconic status in economics. Using criticisms of the NOFIA by John Searle, Amartya Sen, Hilary Putnam, Vivian Walsh and Julius Kovesi, as well as the critical realist method of explanatory critique, the paper argues for a form of moral realism. 1 The author expresses appreciation to two anonymous referees for correcting errors and making helpful suggestions. The usual caveat, of course, applies.
5th International Scientific Conference: All About People Conference Proceedings with Peer-Review. , 2017
Normative theories of ethics are many, yet none seem to be broad enough so as to provide a maxim by which one can act and always do so rightly. However, at the same time, each seems to be too broad such that they allow for problems and do not hold up in individual cases. This paper proposes a new distinction that allows us to account for individual situations as well as general maxims and principles which one might and/or should hold-the distinction between moral 'oughts' and pragmatic 'bests'. The former references the normative claims on what one should do, the latter, the things which are most appropriate for the given situation and the particular individual. The foundation for this distinction rests in a moral fact regarding the connectedness of all things and established the moral principle that we should act so as to promote the general understanding of this most crucial moral fact.
Argumentation, 2000
Many philosophers claim that no formally valid argument can have purely non-normative premises and a normative or moral conclusion that occurs essentially. Mark Nelson recently proposed a new counterexample to this Humean doctrine:
2007
1. Introduction 2. The Sceptical Argument 3. Norms and Normativity 4. The Sceptical Solution 5. Reductionism 6. Anti-Reductionism 7. Prescriptivity 8. Conclusion Bibliography Prescriptivity
This paper argues against ought implies can (OIC) by the use of two independent objections. The first objection is a consideration of two counterexamples to the principle of OIC provided by Moti Mizrahi. An evaluation of Mizrahi’s counterexamples motivates one of my own, which is taken to be more intuitively persuasive. The second objection to OIC utilizes Frankfurtian counterexamples to the principle of alternative possibilities (PAP). Although Frankfurt himself does not believe his counterexamples to PAP also work against OIC, further analysis shows PAP does analytically entail OIC, thus, counterexamples to the former work against the latter as well.
Ratio Juris, 2024
This article examines the application of the ought-implies-can principle in the legal domain, especially in the relationship between obligations and responsibility. It addresses the challenge of cases in which an agent cannot do what is required of her, and yet it seems plausible to say that she has an obligation. To deal with these cases, two parallel distinctions are made: between rules of conduct and rules of imputation, and between doings and things done. It is proposed that these distinctions show that the principle operates in two different but complementary ways: as part of prescriptive relations and as part of responsibility practices.
Synthese, 2011
What is the relation between what we ought to do, on the one hand, and our epistemic access to the ought-giving facts, on the other? In assessing this, it is common to distinguish 'objective' from 'subjective' oughts. Very roughly, on the objectivist conception what an agent ought to do is determined by ought-giving facts in such a way that does not depend on the agent's beliefs about, or epistemic access to, those facts; whereas on the subjectivist conception, what an agent ought to do depends on his beliefs. This paper defends the need for, and explicates, a third category of 'ought': 'warranted oughts'. Section 1 introduces the distinction between objective and subjective 'oughts'. Sections 2-3 draw attention to some serious problems with each. Section 4 examines, though rejects, a recent attempt to replace subjective 'oughts' with objective 'wide-scope oughts' operating on belief-action combinations. Section 5 explicates the notion of a warranted 'ought' and defends the account against some possible objections. The resulting a picture is one in which an adequate analysis of practical normativity requires both objective and warranted 'oughts'. Section 6 concludes by responding to a worry about countenancing both.
The debate concerning the proper way of understanding, and hence solving, the “is-ought problem” produced two mutually exclusive positions. One position claims that it is entirely impossible to deduce an imperative statement from a set of factual statements. The other position holds a contrary view to the effect that one can naturally derive an imperative statement from a set of factual statements under certain conditions. Although these two positions have opposing views concerning the problem, it should be evident that they both accept that the “is-ought problem” is concerned with the deducibility of imperative statements from factual statements. Later I will argue that this should not be our concern when we try to make sense of the way we reason about morality
The late work of John Searle opens up a fascinating general theory of the sources of normativity within human civilizations. A classic criticism of Searle’s view reproaches to his “institutionalism” a residual form of conventionalism, preventing Searle to really bridge the gap between contingent facts and ideally universally valid norms. This paper explores an alternative foundation of normativity on “laws of essence” (as opposed to constitutive rules) by answering the crucial question of the place of essences (and values) in a world of facts. Classical phenomenology is shown to be an ontology of concreteness, but this, far from making it irrelevant to the foundation of ideals and norms – even practical, ethical, political ones – makes it the philosophy of ideals, and relative “oughts”, par excellence.
Ethical theory and moral practice, 2012
Morality and rationality are both normative: the moral claim "you ought to help others" is a genuine normative judgment, as well as the prudential maxim "you ought to brush your teeth twice a day". But it seems that there is a crucial difference these two judgments. In the first part of this paper, I argue that this difference is to be understood as a difference between two kinds of normativity: demanding and recommending normativity. But the crucial task is, of course, to explain the difference. In the second part of this paper, I suggest that metaethical expressivists can provide a good explanation: by extending the analysis of ordinary (nonnormative) demands and recommendations to normative judgments, they can formulate a convincing account that captures the key differences between morality and rationality.
Business Ethics Quarterly, 2015
In this article we investigate a philosophical problem for normative business ethics theory suggested by a phenomenon that contemporary psychologists call “bounded ethicality,” which can be identified with the putative fact that well-intentioned people, constrained by psychological limitations, make ethical choices inconsistent with their own ethical beliefs and commitments. When one combines the idea that bounded ethicality is pervasive with the idea that a person morally ought to do something only if she can, it raises a doubt about the practical relevance of the moral principles that business ethics theory prescribes. We call this doubt the Radical Behavioral Challenge. It consists in the idea that people cannot generally conform to the normative ethical principles that business ethics theorists prescribe, and that these principles are therefore practically irrelevant. We answer the Radical Behavioral Challenge and explore normative implications of our answer.
Logique et Analyse
A belief is correct if and only if the believed proposition is true. Some philosophers argued that from this standard of correctness it is possible to derive the statement of a norm, a claim about what a subject ought to do. Many formulations of the standard in terms of an ‘ought’-claim have been suggested, but all resulted affected by some problem. My aim in this article is to suggest a new formulation of the standard in ‘ought’-terms based on an analysis of the relations occurring between the notions of correctness and ‘ought’. My suggested formulation is that, for any subject S and proposition p, according to the standard of correctness, given that S believes that p, it ought to be that p.
Sanne Taekema, Bart van Klink and Wouter de Been (eds.), Facts and Norms in Law, Edward Elgar 2016, p. 23-49, 2016
Philosophical and methodological discussions with regard to normative and value judgment presuppose the availability of a set of clear concepts by means of which these discussions can be made fruitful. To provide such a framework, or at least its beginnings, the present paper makes and explains distinctions between, amongst others, facts and descriptions thereof, kinds of objectivity of facts, deontic facts and norms, kinds of deontic facts, kinds of rules, and facts and values. By means of some examples, the usefulness of the clear concepts for methodological issues is illustrated.
2021
Haji argues that determinism threatens deontic morality, not via a threat to moral responsibility, but directly, because of the principle that “ought” implies “can”. Haji’s argument requires not only that we embrace an “ought” implies “can” principle, but also that we adopt the principle that “ought” implies “able not to”. I argue that we have little reason to adopt the latter principle, and examine whether deontic morality might be destroyed on the basis of the more commonly embraced “ought” implies “can” principle alone. I argue that despite what look like initially compelling reasons why we might suppose that this weaker conclusion is similarly destructive to deontic morality, we actually have good reason to doubt that it has any practical relevance for moral deliberation at all.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.