Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2004, Journal of Human Rights
This paper presents an argument against using singular notions of refugee in research. By mapping the historical and contemporary relationships between refugeehood and citizenship and by outlining the norms and ontologies underpinning the mainstream academic notions of refugee, I aim to show the deficiencies of singular notions. As an alternative, I propose conceptualizing the refugee based on multiple norms. My overall argument against singular notions of refugee is that they fail to identify and recognize certain human sufferings which are constitutive ofthe refugee condition. This is also true for the 1951 Geneva Convention's singular definition of a refugee. The theoretical and ethical shortfalls of singular approaches arise from this failure in spite ofthe fact that protection of human rights is their earnesdy declared goal. More specifically, the problem of singular approaches is that they are primarily derived from particular citizenship ideals, political visions and images of person. The predicament is that different citizenship ideals construe different couplings between citizenship and refugeehood. Sufferings that are recognized as the fundament ofthe refugee condition vary between paradigms. When refugeehood and citizenship are conceptually tied to each other, human sufferings that constitute the refugee condition are conceived in terms of citizenship ideals' ontological assumptions rather than actual human sufferings. Defining the refugee in terms of citizenship ideals is, thus, detrimental to social analysis. By tying the notion of refugee to normatively defined citizen ideals, one detaches it from human rights. The coupling between citizenship and refugeehood substantiates aporetic questions such as whether states should prioritize their obligations to their citizens or assume their responsibility for refugees. Only when the refugee is defined in terms of citizenship ideals and 'as a function ofthe interstate system' (Sassen 1999) can such questions be vindicated. However, the foundation of refugee rights is the idea of universal human rights, which predates the emergence of citizenship (Betten and Grieff 1998). The question is not about states' having to choose between their citizens' claims and foreigners' claims; it is about choosing between citizens' claims for a better life and refiigees' claims for a life at all. This is a choice between citizens' rights obtained in exchange for their performance of some duties and individuals' inalienable natural rights which they have by virtue of being humans. Citizenship rights and human rights are thus two substantially different orders of rights which are not comparable, although receiving states' citizens may perceive the emotional, cultural, social, and economic consequences of protecting refugees as a threat to their own well-being. By conceptualizing the refugee in terms of citizenship, one trivializes and misses this crucial point about the refugee condition. When the question is put as a choice between a better life and a life at all, we are in the domain of individuals' inalienable human rights.
Michigan journal of international law, 1982
Draft, please do not quote. Hannah Arendt was perhaps the first to outline the thought of the refugee as an exemplary figure for a political order organised as a plurality of territorially bounded sovereign states. This in the sense not only that the refugee is best conceived as a distinctively modern political artefact of the international society of states, but also that the exceptional status of refugee is one of the political media through which the normative structure of this order of governance is reproduced. Arendt's thought has been both supported and elaborated by recent historical studies of the institution of refugeehood, perhaps most notably by Nevzat Soguk and Emma Haddad, but its implications for normative reflection on this modern institution have not, I think, been widely taken up. My strategy is, then, to try to make plausible a view of the international refugee regime which is not constructed in terms of humanitarian obligations but, rather, in terms of political obligations that arise as conditions of the political legitimacy of the international society of states considered as a global regime of governance, and to draw out the normative implications of this view for the institution of refugeehood and distribution of responsibility for refugees. In other words, I want to make a case for the claim that that we can rationally reconstruct the normative grounds and character of the international refugee regime in terms that require reference only to basic or minimum conditions of legitimacy of states and of the international society of states. Refugeehood, as I have already noted, is an exceptional status in that a person claiming this status from a state which is not their own (and which acts as the relevant representative of the international society of states) is entitled to a fair determination of whether they satisfy the relevant criteria and, if so, the state to which they have made application has a duty to ensure that they are not exposed to the relevant threat (typically, but not necessarily, through a grant of asylum in that state). What makes this status exceptional is that the refugee is entitled to the protection of a state which is not their own in the context of a governmental norm that states are fundamentally responsible to, and for, their own citizens. As Matthew Gibney has noted: Above all else … the state is fundamentally an answer to the question of who is responsible to whom in the modern world: states are responsible to their own citizens. The survival of the state as an entity over time rests, moreover, on its ability to portray itself convincingly as an answer to such a question. As a consequence, the claims of outsiders are assessed by states, including liberal democratic ones, through a logic that deprecates the interests and needs of outsiders – a logic that is exceedingly sensitive to the potential damage to its own authority involved in forcing its citizens to incur costs for the sake of strangers. Modern states are highly resistant to the moral claims of outsiders. (2004: 211)
Journal of Refugee Studies, 2010
The concept of State responsibility is as old as the human civilization. It has been the perennial responsibility of the State to protect the life and liberty of its citizenry. Today an individual has become central to the entire human rights discourse and is being regarded as a subject of International Law. Moreover, national boundaries are losing their meaning. Consequently a new world human order is being emplaced. The human rights of all individuals including that of refugees have become a polemical debate heralding a new premise whereat state concerns and individual rights are at loggerhead with each other. In this conspectus, it is incumbent upon the state to reconcile this paradox in an age of transnationalisation of human rights and civil liberties. Asylum countries are not as much responsible as country of origin. Thus, country of origin should squarely be held responsible for the refugees' flows and it is the responsibility of the refugee generating state not to create problems of galling proportions for the other states as it is contrary to the notion of a civilized state. The responsibility of the country of origin is higher than the responsibility of state of reception under the International Law.
This essay develops, within the terms of the recent New York Declaration, an account of the shared responsibility of states to refugees and of how the character of that responsibility effects the ways in which it can be fairly shared. However, it also moves beyond the question of the general obligations that states owe to refugees to consider ways in which refugee choices and refugee voice can be given appropriate standing with the global governance of refuge. It offers an argument for the normative significance of refugee's reasons for choosing states of asylum and linked this to consideration of a refugee matching system and to refugee quota trading conceived as responsibility-trading, before turning to the issue of the inclusion of refugee voice in relation to the justification of the norms of refugee governance and in relation to the institutions and practices of refugee governance through which those norms are given practical expression. " We commit to a more equitable sharing of the burden and responsibility for hosting and supporting the world's refugees. "
Review of International Studies
Refugees are often considered as a source of disorder if not fundamental threat to international society. In contrast, and drawing from an English School approach, this article argues that the figure of the refugee is foundational to the constitution of both modern international society and its agent, the sovereign territorial state; hence refugee protection represents a primary institution of international society. Starting with conceptual and methodological considerations for studying primary institutions, the article then highlights the longstanding and widespread state practice of granting asylum. It is shown that on the one hand, the figure of the refugee serves to consolidate and naturalise the nation/state/territory trinity underpinning the modern state system; and on the other hand, protecting refugees plays a central role in the construction of statist self-identities as liberal, humanitarian, and altruistic agents. The last section of the article turns to the politics of c...
Nordic Journal of International Law, 1990
Refugee Law is built upon the legal foundation of the 1951 Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees and the following 1967 amending Protocol. These documents assume, prima facia, the inviolability of state sovereignty, as expressed in the UN Charter, which “is based on the principle of the sovereign equality of all its Members” . These principles include non-intervention in the affairs of other states, and the sacrosanct nature of Westphalian borders. Refugee Law presupposes these notions, and constructs its legal framework accordingly
Europe has been recently shaken by the great number of persons coming from Syria and neighbouring countries which were calling themselves "refugees". According to the United Nations Refugee Agency, since 2015 more than 1 million refugees travelled to Greece. This paper aims to analyze the notion of "refugees" in light of international legal instruments applicable and to draw up distinctions between different categories of migrant persons and those who are really refugees and may apply for international protection under the 1951 UN Convention on refugees. The distinction regarding the use of terms is relevant for shaping the legal status of different persons who leave their country of origin.
The refugees are on the tassels of municipal and international legal systems since the adoption of an international legal framework secured as the 1951 UN Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees (UNCSR) that has been developed to provide refugees some protection which is now debated to address all their grievances including the refugee status determination (RSD) in every nook and corner of the world. RSD is the process whereunder states and UNHCR determine who are entitled to have the benefits of refugee protection. The RSD process facilitates the accomplishment of their global human rights obligations to the beneficiaries under the international refugee protection regime. It is a platitude of international refugee law (IRL) that RSD does not bestow status on a refugee but merely validates it. In performing the RSD obligations, it is the treatment that is meted out to refugees and outsiders in our midst within the UNCSR refugee definition. The instant research paper addresses the issues of critical spaces in the RSD system based on the grounds envisaged in the refugee definition that poses challenges, risks, and responses for a cosmopolitan purpose. There is also a sovereignty narrative that has made the human rights subservient and the menace of persecution is being ignored within the synthesis of International Human Rights Law (IHRL), International Humanitarian Law (IHL) and International Refugee Law (IRL). However, there is also a pressing question of a legal framework for the protection of refugees frontier justice for them globally that address every aspect of the refugee problem from registration and determination of status, to repatriation, resettlement and legal and political protection reassessment, interpretation, responses, risks, and challenges worldwide.
AmeriQuests, 2019
ASEJ Scientific Journal of Bielsko-Biala School of Finance and Law, 2018
In the paper the author attempts to describe the issue of refugees as a very important problem in international law, a problem which generates profits e.g. a rise in human capital, as well as losses e.g. costs, for the countries involved. The balance depends on the policy of a given country, whether this country is able to capitalize on the human capital or whether it is only counting costs. Sometimes obligations resulting from international law are not sufficient to convince societies that accepting refugees is the right decision. The paper will focus on how, with appropriate legislative tools, the united world can help people who are in danger. The author will also pose a question whether enough is being done, or whether the scope and methods currently in use should be amended. The paper discusses the issue of refugees from the perspective of various organizations involved i.e. global institutions like UNHCR, European Union institutions, non-government organizations (NGOs) and con...
Berkeley Journal of International Law, 2012
Many scholars of international refugee law assert that there is no definition of refugee under international law except that given in the Refugee Convention. This assertion, however, overlooks the dynamic way that the Refugee Convention is interpreted and is usually made without a detailed analysis of customary international law. This article attempts to address this shortcoming in the literature by examining conventional and customary international law contributing to the contemporary definition of refugee. Furthermore, it will attempt to do this is an even-handed manner, concluding that the definition has expanded in favor of claimants in some aspects, but, actually, contracted against the favor of claimants in others. First, the article will examine the definition of refugee under the Refugee Convention, especially the evolving technique for interpreting the Convention, to determine whether the definition has outgrown its conventional shell. Second, the article will undertake a comprehensive analysis of state practice and opinio juris on this question, examining the most up-to-date sources. In particular, it will reflect on the role of specially interested or specially affected states in the formation of customary international law and the growth of “subsidiary” protection. Also the article will consider the contribution of the practice and opinio juris of international organizations in the frame of the contemporary international law’s understanding of the contribution international organizations can make. Lastly, the article will look at the opposite side of the coin: the ways in which customary international law may have narrowed the definition beyond the terms of the Refugee Convention. It will conclude by proposing the new definition of a refugee under conventional and customary international law based on the findings.
1982
A refugee leaves the country of his or her national origin because the political community will not or can no longer vouchsafe the refugee\u27s life, liberty, or peace of mind. In many cases, the sovereign of national origin actively and coercively deprives the refugee of those basic components of human dignity. By taking flight, refugees enter a precarious realm between sovereigns. They may no longer rely upon the solicitude of their native sovereign, yet international law gives them no effective replacement for that power. They gain neither a right to asylum in other countries nor one to the assumption of a new nationality. Yet only the tie of nationality furnishes the full protection of international law, since individuals as such have no rights under that body of law. Covenants on the status of refugees and stateless persons and the organization of the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR) have not changed this aspect of the world order
This paper takes up the questions of (1) how the refugee crisis exhibits the fault lines in what might otherwise seem to be a robust human rights regime and (2) what kinds of ways of seeing and thinking might better attune us to solving these problems. There is surprising agreement internationally on the content of human rights, although there is a huge gulf between international agreements on human rights and the protection of those most vital. The subtitle of the paper, " another stab at universal rights, " has a double entendre: in the midst of a crisis that is stabbing international agreements on human rights to its core, I will take a stab at using the crisis situation to point a way forward toward a cosmopolitan social imaginary that uses human imagination, not just as an ability to represent in one's mind what one has seen elsewhere, but also as an ability to imagine something radically new. This social imaginary points to the necessity of according everyone, refugees included, as having a right to politics and thus a hand in shaping their own world, including their new, host communities.
Routledge, 2020
The book provides an in-depth discussion of democratic theory questions in relation to refugee law. The work introduces readers to the evolution of refugee law and its core issues today, as well as central lines in the debate about democracy and migration. Bringing together these fields, the book links theoretical considerations and legal analysis. Based on its specific understanding of the refugee concept, it offers a reconstruction of refugee law as constantly confronted with the question of how to secure rights to those who have no voice in the democratic process. In this reconstruction, the book highlights, on the one hand, the need to look beyond the legal regulations for understanding the challenges and gaps in refugee protection. It is also the structural lack of political voice, the book argues, which shapes the refugee’s situation. On the other hand, the book opposes a view of law as mere expression of power and points out the dynamics within the law which reflect endeavors towards mitigating exclusion. The book will be essential reading for academics and researchers working in the areas of migration and refugee law, legal theory and political theory. Table of Contents: Introduction I. The refugee Chapter 1 Who is a refugee? Chapter 2 Who decides who is a refugee? II. Democracy’s edges Chapter 3 Citizenship and the claiming of rights Chapter 4 Democracy between the need for institutions and demands of inclusion III. The legal conditions of refugees’ political voice Chapter 5 Institutions of refugees’ political participation Chapter 6 The role of associative rights for refugees’ political voice Chapter 7 Humanitarian government and the political membership of refugees Chapter 8 Representation of refugees in international forums Outlook
This paper was written while I was a Marie Curie Fellow at the Migration Research Center Mirekoc and the Department of International Relations at Koc University, Istanbul, Turkey. I am grateful to the Director of the Center, Ahmed Icduygu, and the colleagues from the Center for their support. The research leading to these results has received funding from the European Union's Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007-2013) under grant agreement n° 316796 The recent Syrian refugee crisis opened a debate on the under-theorized issue of migration law regarding the status and the rights of refugees and asylum seekers. According to UNHCR estimates, Turkey has, since the conflict in Syria begun, accommodated within its jurisdictional boundaries the most conspicuous number of refugees (around two million), but none of them have been recognized legally as refugees. Turkey, one of the signatory states of the 1951 Geneva Convention, still applies “geographical limitations”; that is, it does not grant refugee status to non-European to- be refugees, but rather extends to the latter a status of ‘temporary protection’. The paradox is that Turkey grants legal refugee status to European applicants (consider the very trivial number of applicants in need of refuge from Europe after 1951), whereas millions of non-European ‘proper’ refugees, including those currently in the country will not be granted refugee status. What can we learn philosophically from this law and practice? Most philosophers concur with granting refugees a fundamental human right, in line with the Kantian hospitality principle, to sojourn in other territories temporarily and also more permanently, including a lifetime. The principle is incorporated in the Geneva Convention on the Status of Refugees, as the principle of “non-refoulement” (United Nations, 1951), obliging signatory states not to forcibly return refugees and asylum seekers to their countries of origin, if doing so would endanger their lives. Furthermore, asylum seekers’ and refugees’ claims to admission and more broadly to human rights protection are legally incorporated in the international human rights regime, and subsequently accepted by states (Benhabib, 2004). The fundamental human right to admission regards the admission of the asylee and refugee, and not that of immigrants whose admission remains “a privilege”, in the sense that it is up to the sovereign to grant such a “contract of beneficence” (Benhabib 2004). David Miller argues that when it comes to protecting human rights, states’ actions should reflect primarily the ‘terms’ of states, as they see fit: “your human right to food could at most impose on me an obligation to provide adequate food in the form that is most convenient to me (i.e. it costs me the least labour to produce), not an obligation to provide food in the form that you happen to prefer”; furthermore, states do not have a duty to automatically admit refugees, if for example, other similarly well off states can admit them, and the principle of non-refoulement is fulfilled (Miller, 2013). Miller rules out the theoretical possibility of human rights violations, in claiming that a state can deny entry to refugees, only if they are not returned to the country of origin and third countries where their human rights will be violated, and provided that some other state would take charge of them. Miller’s state-centrist view, assuming the point of view of states primarily, and second, wrongly assuming that the only theoretically salient feature is when refugees do not receive admission, as a result of which their human rights are violated, has pernicious implications. As an alternative, I argue that human rights are possible primarily when we view their defence as a primary moral concern, rather than instrumental and contingent upon what states see fit. I propose instead a philosophical view that genuinely assumes and acts upon the needs of refugees primarily, in both being admitted and rejected to sojourn in new territories. Very little effort has so far been expended by migration theorists to explain the character of a just distribution of refugees between states. Most studies instead have offered ample explanations regarding why refugees and migrants move to some states rather than others (Gibney, 2009). Since an adequate baseline from which to judge the justice of the distribution of refugees between states is still lacking, any new patterns of movement we might advocate creates possibilities for new unjust distribution patterns, a normative scrutiny that takes into consideration justice to refugees (besides justice between states) is of paramount importance. In this paper I analyse few of the main proposals of refugee distribution among states from a perspective of justice and argue in favour of the burden-sharing model that prioritizes justice to refugees. Specifically, I briefly analyse the “Syrian refugee crises” and I conceptualize it as an “engineered regionalism”, according to which the most conspicuous number of refugees end up seeking refuge in the region of their origin. In the second section, I explain why engineered regionalism is problematic from a justice perspective, and therefore explore alternatives we commonly think of in the literature as burden-sharing options. In the third section I argue that the respective alternatives are also morally unsatisfactory. They are all based on the presupposition that a right to free movement is what will entitle the refugee to (re)- settle to the country of one’s choosing, whereas this right is grounded on a philosophically informed principle of non-refoulement (as the ‘fire’ illustration proves). I attempt in the last section to propose a new model that is informed by the latter principle.
There is a lively debate about how to define refugeehood, for instance about the question whether an individual fleeing hunger is a refugee. This paper argues against the two most prominent characterizations of refugeehood. Both characterize the refugee by reference to a duty - either to the duty to admit (e.g., Lister) or to the less concrete duty to protect (e.g., Shacknove). However, both are inadequate from the perspective of commonsense as well as for moral and political purposes, I argue, since both imply that, when two individuals are fleeing threats of the same kind, only one of them may be a refugee. This result is due to the fact that duties depend partly on the capacities and decisions of duty-bearers, as well as on the needs of third parties. Much more plausibly, a refugee is defined simply as a person whose basic needs and rights are threatened and who migrates with the aim to find protection. Although this definition coheres with commonsense, it has so far been neglected in the philosophical and political debate.
King's Law Journal, 2014
Contemporary Issues in Refugee Law is a collection that attempts to do at least two thingsexpose a number of challenges faced by contemporary refugee law practice and position refugee law's central concepts and institutions in the context of a rapidly changing world. The contributors use a wide range of examples to demonstrate that aspects of the refugee system will need to be rethought, some incrementally and some radically if, as editors Satvinder Juss and Colin Harvey note, it is to remain relevant in contemporary times (1). The book is organised into three main parts ("Of Refugee 'Crisis', Normative 'Soft Laws' and 'Human Rights'", "Of the Advent of New Refugees" and "Of the Securitization, Exclusion and Internal Relocation of Refugees"). This breakdown of the contributions allows for a relatively straightforward thread of critique, beginning with the framing of refugee law in contemporary times, then following on to review the doctrinal and institutional challenges faced by various groups of applicants and closing with a critical assessment of the limits placed on refugee protection. The first of the three main sections frames refugee law as a regime in crisis (13). Catherine Dauvergne in "Refugee law as perpetual crisis" uses the vernacular of crisis to describe the paradigm from within which refugees are viewed, both in terms of how their plights are represented (fleeing from crisis)(14) as well as what she terms 'crisis bias', or the centrality of the crises of the urgent escape or the noteworthy drama of regime change within successful refugee claims (15-16). This contribution provides a timely echo of the work of Hilary Charlesworth, who described international law as a 'discipline in crisis'. While Charlesworth argues the disadvantages of such a crisis model, Dauvergne departs from this sentiment and suggests that the crisis paradigm when applied to refugee law, unlike human rights law more generally, serves the important purpose of maintaining the value of refugee law-and that while the crisis embodied by refugees and the system of international refugee law must be resisted, to 'resolve' the crisis would 'make refugees disappear' and eliminate the critical potential of the constant tension and resistance caused by the ill-fit of refugee law within international law and international human rights law (28-31). Satvinder Juss follows in "The UNHCR Handbook in international refugee law" with a depiction of the Handbook as a set of guidelines that the UNHCR intentionally did not make binding or definitive. In light of this fact, Juss argues that interpreting and applying ideas in the Handbook exemplifies the 'politics of knowledge recognition' and that today's legal practitioners and scholars need to both acknowledge why certain aspects of jurisprudence are not codified into 'hard law' on one hand and look beyond 'hard law' to 'soft law' and extra-legal guidance on the other (39-43). Juss ultimately asks whether the Handbook can be rescued as a legal authority. Colin Harvey, in "Is humanity enough? Refugees, asylum seekers and the rights regime", sets out to articulate the pressures that build on the fault-lines between "statist imperatives of migration management and a legal order rooted in notions of guarantees owed to the person" (85). In this endeavour, Harvey argues that examination of the notion of status highlights tensions between a state-centred managerial approach and broader international human rights principles (72-74). He also critically analyses a number of recent cases to demonstrate the nature of decision-making in refugee law-"skilfully crafted calibrations which have notions of balance absorbed into their very language (even while this is strenuously denied)" (85). Despite discussing the concept of 'humanity' in some detail, as well as nodding to Arendt's early critique of human rights as idealist for failing to reconcile with historical contingencies and state power (74), he does not leave the reader with a clear way to understand or use the concept in the scope of his argument. While this is dissatisfying, it has everything to do with the scope of the material (any two-page explanation of 'humanity' will fall short), and it does not detract from exploring the main tensions between state imperatives and international humanitarian norms. Part II of the collection begins with Jason Pobjoy's "A child rights framework for assessing the status of refugee children". Pobjoy advances an analysis which aims to situate
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.