Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
1988, The Journal of Philosophy
An Empire of Thin Air (1988) David Lewis's book, On the Plurality of Worlds, is derived from his 1984 John Locke Lectures, and is the latest word on possible worlds from the discipline's foremost champion of possibilia. It is a serious defense, a priori, of Lewis's notorious doctrines (here called 'modal realism') to the effect that there are tiny purple anthropologists who study human culture unobserved, colossal human-eating monsters 50 feet in height, professional philosophers earning annual salaries in excess of 37 million dollars (pre-inflation), and the like, and that these oddities reside in fabulous alternative universes that are never empirically detected by us (but that are empirically detectable by us). The central idea of Lewis's theory is that whatever might have transpired involving individuals of our universe does indeed transpire in one of these alternative universes, involving counterparts of these individuals (p. 2)-'the principle of plenitude.' Equally critical to Lewis's project is the converse principle that everything that transpires in one of these alternative universes involving our counterparts is something that might have transpired involving ourselves. We may call this 'the principle of moderation.' 1 Together these two principles assert an isomorphism between total ways things might have been with regard to this universe and extant alternative universes, prompting Lewis to identify the former with the latter (p. 86). Lewis thus misleadingly calls his alleged alternative universes 'possible worlds,' and indeed they play a role in Lewis's theory of modal discourse similar in many respects to that of the intensional possible worlds invoked in contemporary philosophical semantics, as conceived of by such writers as Saul Kripke and Robert Stalnaker, that is, maximally specific states or histories. 2 These genuine possible worlds Lewis misleadingly labels 'ersatz worlds.' Like genuine possible worlds, Lewis's alternative universes allegedly 'represent' possible events and states of affairs that might have occurred concerning the individuals of our universe; they are supposed to be entities according to which 1 These principles are not explicitly articulated as I have them. My statement of plenitude is based on a plausible interpretation of Lewis's less explicit formulation. Lewis provides a version of moderation which is closely related to, but much weaker than, the principle formulated here, and which he derives from the trivial modal logical truth that whatever is the case might have been the case (p. 5). This weaker principle, however, is insufficient for Lewis's purposes.
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2012
David Lewis was famous (among other things) for the meta-philosophical claim that knock-down refutations are rare to non-existent in philosophy. You can argue that the costs of a theory exceed the intellectual benefits but it is difficult, if not impossible, to prove that it is false. When it comes to choosing between philosophical theories, it is generally a matter of 'the price is right', and when it comes to refuting a theory the best you can generally do is to drive up the costs whilst diminishing the benefits. There may come a time when the costs are so high and the benefits are so low that the theory can't attract any takers, but this is usually due to a cumulative process of philosophical debate not to a sudden drop in net value brought about by a single decisive counterargument. When philosophers win, it's nearly always a victory on points and almost never a knockout. At the same time, Lewis subscribed to a philosophical thesis so outrageous as to cry out for knock-down refutation, namely that in order to make sense of modal truths, we must postulate an infinity of possible universes, all just as real as the one that we inhabit, but cut off from us in space and time. (This has the corollary that in order to make sense of causality we must postulate an infinity of items that have no causal connection to anything that happens in this universe.) Thus the temptation is to go for the double-whammy, the knock-down refutation of modal realism which is also a counterexample to the metaphilosophical claim. This was our aim when we first drafted this paper, but we can't honestly claim the double victory that we originally hoped for. We may have given Lewis's modal realism a drubbing but we don't pretend to have decked it. Even if we have succeeded in driving up the costs of Lewis's modal realism, it still retains enough benefits to attract some (rational) takers. Thus whatever the fate of Lewis's philosophical thesis, the meta-philosophical claim remains intact. ! We first wrote this article nearly twenty years ago when Lewis himself was very much alive, but for one reason or another we never got around to publishing it. Rather than rewriting it to take account of the sad fact of his death we have decided to leave it in the present tense. We dedicate this paper not only to our friend and colleague, Colin Cheyne (who does not think we should believe in entities which cannot causally affect us), but to the memory of David Lewis, a great philosopher and a great teacher. 2. Modal Realism: Mad Dogs, Milksops and Primitives In his metaphysical summa of 1986, The Plurality of Worlds, (henceforward POW) David Lewis famously defends a doctrine he calls modal realism. The idea is that possible worlds are real, indeed really real. They are concrete entities just like our own world, but cut off from us in space and time. To every logically possible setup there corresponds such a world. Lewis calls this the Principle of Plenitude. In fact, Lewis identifies his worlds with such setups a move which makes it difficult to specify the Principle of Plenitude in a non-circular way (POW, pp. 86-92). Lycan (1988) calls this doctrine 'mad dog' modal realism' 'Rape-and-Loot modal realism' and even 'Nuclear Holocaust modal realism', This is in contrast to moderate, milksop or, as Lewis describes it, ersatz modal realism. Ersatz realists believe in possible worlds all right. It is just that their possible worlds are less ontologically outrageous. Usually, they construct them out of actual entities of some kind: points, sets, sentences or what have you. This is 'paradise on the cheap', since we get all the theoretical advantages of possible worlds without the ontological drawbacks. ! Lewis thinks he can do without modal primitives and that the milksop defenders of ersatz worlds cannot. This he holds to be the drawcard of an otherwise unpalatable theory. His possible worlds are admittedly implausible things (especially in such abundance) and the chief reason for believing in them, rather than in ersatz possibilia of some kind, is that they enable us to eliminate modal primitives. ! Although sometimes denounced as a Meinongian, indeed a relentless Meinongian (Lycan, 1979), Lewis is, in fact, a rather heterodox Quinean. His aim is to explicate the modal concepts in terms of first order logic plus an ontology of possibilia. He retains a Quinean ideology, that is, the conviction that the resources of first-order logic, quantifiers, predicates, truth-functional connectives and the possible assistance of truth and satisfaction, are adequate to describe reality. 1 But unlike Quine (who prefers to believe there are no such things 2) Lewis recognizes modal facts. To accommodate these facts within a Quinean ideology 3 , to explain the modalities in terms of quantification theory, Lewis has to invent more reality. The price of his ideological restraint is ontological inflation. He must posit an infinity of objects to quantify over. But it is important to realize that despite his ontological exuberance, what Lewis is putting forward is a reductive
In the last few decades after having a remarkable career in science-fiction literature possibleworlds and parallel-universes talk became a respectable and useful tool in many areas of philosophical and physical investigations and explanations. In this study I attempt to show the followings.
James Maclaurin ed (2012) Defensor Rationis: Essays in Honor of Colin Cheyne, Dordrecht, Springer , 155-176, 2012
The major selling point of David Lewis’s realism about possible worlds is that the ideological benefits (in Quine’s sense) exceed the ontological costs. By positing concrete possibilia Lewis is able to explain away necessity and possibility, reducing them to the extensional goings on in in a plurality of other (but equally real) universes. We should keep a-hold of possible worlds for fear of meeting something worse, namely primitive modalities. We develop the concept of a spread world, a world - or rather a world description – such that once it is admitted as real, it spreads through logical space excluding alternatives. Some spread worlds such as the Shelleyworld or the Plantingaworld are MODERATELY exclusive, excluding all worlds that lack a certain feature (godlessness in the case of the Shelleyworld or God in the case of the Plantingaworld). Others such as the Lutherworld are HIGHLY exclusive, ruling out all worlds but one. But all are a threat to s plenitude and some are a threat to consistency. Our basic claim is that it is difficult for Lewis to exclude spread worlds without the aid of a modal primitive, thus forfeiting the chief advantage of his theory. There is, perhaps, a way out. He can deny that there is a world corresponding to every coherent description (thus avoiding inconsistency) without specifying WHICH coherent descriptions don’t describe worlds (thus avoiding a modal primitive). But this makes him a bit like the sleazy set theorist who avoids Russell’s paradox by denying the unrestricted comprehension axiom whilst refusing to say which formulae define sets and which don’t. Nonetheless, we cannot claim the knockout polemical victory that we had originally hoped for, thus confirming Lewis’s maxim that knock-out polemical victories are rare to non-existent in philosophy.
auslegung: a journal of philosophy
Philosophy Compass, 2009
It is difficult to wander far in contemporary metaphysics without bumping into talk of possible worlds. And reference to possible worlds is not confined to metaphysics. It can be found in contemporary epistemology and ethics, and has even made its way into linguistics and decision theory. What are those possible worlds, the entities to which theorists in these disciplines all appeal? This paper sets out and evaluates a leading contemporary theory of possible worlds, David Lewis's Modal Realism. I note two competing ambitions for a theory of possible worlds: that it be reductive and user-friendly. I then outline Modal Realism and consider objections to the effect that it cannot satisfy these ambitions. I conclude that there is some reason to believe that Modal Realism is not reductive and overwhelming reason to believe that it is not user-friendly.
2013
The paper outlines and immediately discusses the so-called 'soft' impossibility, i.e., non-logical impossibility generated by modal realism. It will be shown that although in a particular case genuine modal realism, straightforwardly applied, deems impossible a proposition that other philosophers have claimed to be (intuitively) possible, there is a variety of methodologically acceptable moves available in order to avoid the problem. The impossibility at issue is the existence of island universes. Given the Lewisian analysis there are three points at which we might try to square genuine modal realism with such a controversial and problematic claim of (im)possibility, namely: a) the contraction of our pre-theoretical opinions about possibility, b) the revision of some Lewisian definitions and/or c) the extension of our ontological commitments. I shall look at each of these approaches applied to the problematic case.
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2012
Among the most remarkable developments in metaphysics since the 1950's is the explosion of philosophical interest in possible worlds. This paper proposes an explanation of what possible worlds are, and argues that this proposal, the interpreted models conception, should be attractive to anyone who thinks that modal facts are primitive, and so not to be explained in terms of some non-modal notion of "possible world." I articulate three constraints on any acceptable primitivist explanation of the nature of possible worlds, and show that the interpreted models conception meets the three constraints. there were and what they were like. 1 Providing a non-modal explanation of the notion of being a possible world has occupied center stage in the thought of these philosophers. It will not, however, occupy center stage here. We are not going to require here that the notion of being a possible world be explained in thoroughly non-modal terms. Suppose, then, that modal primitivism is true: some modal facts cannot be reduced to, or even explained in terms of, any congeries of exclusively non-modal facts. Even granting that (SC) does not provide fodder for an explanation of modal facts in non-modal terms, there remain a number of alternative views of (SC)'s significance. One could suggest, for instance, that instances of (SC) are simply meaningless, since they all crucially employ the notion of being a possible world, and that notion has not been explained. Alternatively, one could simply deny that there are any possible worlds. Then there will be instances of (SC)-those involving true possibility claims-that are false. If we take either of these skeptical lines, then much of contemporary modal metaphysics will turn out to be either meaningless or a pack of falsehoods. And other disciplines that make liberal use of possible worlds, e.g. some strands of linguistics, ethics, epistemology, and decision theory, will suffer from the same defect. 2 This need not imply that talk of possible worlds in all of these
The epistemology of modality is gradually coming to play a central role in general discussions about modality. This paper is a contribution in this direction, in particular I draw a comparison between Lewis's Modal realism and Timothy Wil-liamson's recent account of modality in terms of counterfactual thinking. In order to have criteria of evaluation, I also formulate four requirements which are supposed to be met by any theory of modality to be epistemologically adequate.
Unpublished manuscript, 2008
This is a DRAFT. Do not cite without permission. Comments, criticism and suggestions welcome.
Philosophical Studies, 2014
In this paper, after clarifying certain features of Gideon Rosen's Modal Fictionalism, I raise two problems for that view and argue that these problems strongly suggest that advocates of a ''Deflationist Strategy'' ought not to endorse, or adopt Rosen-style Modal Fictionalism. Keywords Fictionalism Á Modality Á Possible worlds Á Deflationism Á Revolutionary fictionalism Á Hermeneutic fictionalism Á Universals Á Properties Many philosophers are uncomfortable with the very notion, let alone accepting the existence, of possible worlds. At the same time, however, they recognize the benefits of the possible-worlds analysis of modal discourse. 1 In particular, they appreciate the rigor and clarity that this analysis brings to an otherwise complicated and unclear way of talking. While the concreteness or ''worldliness'' of so-called possible worlds is a matter of debate, it is widely accepted that the quantification over possible worlds that this analysis of modal discourse involves brings with it an ontological commitment to some kind of entity, picked out with the expression 'possible worlds'. While David Lewis has argued mightily for what he (1986) calls modal realism-the view that possible worlds should be understood as separate, individual, concrete universes that are as fully genuine and realized as the cosmos we inhabit-many find this view of possible worlds (as opposed to the view that the things modal discourse involves quantifying over are abstract, complex properties or
Dialetheism and its Applications, ed. A Reiger and G Young, Springer (Trends in logic), 2020
David Lewis famously dismisses genuine impossible worlds on the basis that a contradiction bound within the scope of his modifier ‘at w’ amounts to a contradiction tout court – an unacceptable consequence. Motivated by the rising demand for impossible worlds in philosophical theorising, this paper examines whether anything coherent can be said about an extension of Lewis’ theory of genuine, concrete possible worlds into genuine, concrete impossible worlds. Lewis’ reasoning reveals two ways to carve out conceptual space for the genuinely impossible. The first is to abandon Lewis’ classical translation schema for negation, on the basis that it begs the question against incomplete and inconsistent worlds. I argue that, whilst this option incurs some loss in the semantics, it preserves the core spirit of Lewis’ metaphysics. The alternative is to bite the bullet, abandon classical logic and embrace true contradictions. The key challenge with this strategy is that the resulting theory seems committed to a particularly strong kind of dialetheism — one that even dialetheists would be reluctant to accept. I motivate such a dialethic account of genuine impossibilia using Lewis’ own methodology and defend it against triviality objections. I close with a few comments on why impossible worlds should not be reduced to set theoretic constructs out of possible worlds.
The Metaphysics Within Physics, 2007
The Philosophical Quarterly, 2010
Accounts of propositions as sets of possible worlds have been criticized for conflating distinct impossible propositions. In response to this problem, some have proposed to introduce impossible worlds to represent distinct impossibilities, endorsing the thesis that impossible worlds must be of the same kind; this has been called the parity thesis. I show that this thesis faces problems, and propose a hybrid account which rejects it: possible worlds are taken as concrete Lewisian worlds, and impossibilities are represented as set-theoretic constructions out of them. This hybrid account (1) distinguishes many intuitively distinct impossible propositions; (2) identifies impossible propositions with extensional constructions; (3) avoids resorting to primitive modality, at least so far as Lewisian modal realism does.
Metaphysica, 2011
A major criticism of David Lewis’ counterfactual theory of causation is that it allows too many things to count as causes, especially since Lewis allows, in addition to events, absences to be causes as well. Peter Menzies has advanced this concern under the title “the problem of profligate causation.” In this paper, I argue that the problem of profligate causation provides resources for exposing a tension between Lewis’ acceptance of absence causation and his modal realism. The result is a different problem of profligate causation—one that attacks the internal consistency of Lewisian metaphysics rather than employing common sense judgments or intuitions that conflict with Lewis’ extensive list of causes.
2020
The aim of the present book is to argue that even impossible things happen. By taking David Lewis’s Modal realism (hen- ceforth as “Mr”) seriously, i claim that besides infinitely many concrete ways things could have been, there exist ways things could not have been. i call them concrete impossible worlds.
Acta Analytica, 2022
Necessitism is the controversial thesis that necessarily everything is necessarily something, namely that everything, everywhere, necessarily exists. What is controversial about necessitism is that, at its core, it claims that things could not have failed to exist, while we have a pre-theoretical intuition that not everything necessarily exists. Contingentism, in accordance with common sense, denies necessitism: it claims that some things could have failed to exist. Timothy Williamson is a necessitist and claims that David Lewis is a necessitist too. The paper argues that, granted the assumptions that lead to interpret the Lewisian as a necessitist, she can preserve contingentist intuitions, by genuinely agreeing with the folk that existence is contingent. This is not just the uncontroversial claim that the Lewisian, as a result of the prevalence of restricted quantification in counterpart theoretic regimentations of natural language, can agree with the folk while disagreeing with t...
Metaphysica, 2014
It is a commonsense thesis that unactualized possibilities are not parts of actuality. To keep his modal realism in line with this thesis, David Lewis employed his indexical account of the term “actual.” I argue that the addition of counterpart theory to Lewis’s modal realism undermines his strategy for respecting the commonsense thesis. The case made here also reveals a problem for Lewis’s attempt to avoid haecceitism.
Doctoral Dissertation, 2023
According to actualism about possible worlds everything that exists is actual. Possible worlds and individuals are actually existing abstract parts of the actual world. Aristotelian actualism is a view that there are only actual individuals but no possible ones, nor their individual abstract representatives. Because of that, our actualist account of modality should differ depending on whether it concerns actual individuals or possible ones. The main goal of the dissertation is to develop a metaphysical framework for Aristotelian actualism. Chapter 1 explains basic issues associated with the possible world approach to modality. I overview modal realist and actualist views on possible worlds and explain why I support the actualist approach. Subsequently, I introduce a distinction between Platonic and Aristotelian actualism, and discuss some semantic issues associated with actualism as such. In Chapter 2 I argue that Aristotelian actualism, modeled on linguistic ersatzism, is preferable over its Platonic counterpart. Subsequently, I propose a metaphysical framework for Aristotelian ersatzism which is based on a claim that our modal concepts work differently for actual and possible individuals. In order to explain that claim I introduce three specific differences concerning modal features of actual and possible individuals: (a) Representational Difference, according to which actual and possible individuals are represented differently by possible worlds; (b) Metaphysical Difference, according to which actual and possible individuals are represented by possible worlds as having different metaphysical nature; (c) Modal Difference, which says while there are singular and contingent possibilities involving actual individuals, all possibilities about possible individuals are general and necessary. I propose to interpret those differences in terms of the doctrines of haecceitism, antihaecceitism and existentialism. There is however no consensus on how those views should be characterized. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 focus on providing a precise characterization of those doctrines. Chapter 3 focuses on the doctrines of modal haecceitism and antihaecceitism, which I view as opposite accounts of how possible worlds represent possibilities. According to modal haecceitism what possible worlds say about particular individuals does not supervene on what they say qualitatively. Modal antihaecceitism is a denial of such a claim. Chapter 4 concerns metaphysical haecceitism and antihaecceitism, which I take to be alternative accounts of the fundamental structure of reality. For the metaphysical haecceitist reality contains irreducible singular facts, while for the metaphysical antihaecceitist reality is purely qualitative and general. Chapter 5 focuses on an argument between existentialists and antiexistentialists. Existentialists claim that there are contingent singular propositions, while antiexistentialists deny that. I defend existentialism against antiexistentialist counterarguments, as well as criticize some of the antiexistentialist accounts of singular propositions modeled on the notion of individual essence. In Chapter 6, by appealing to the results of investigations conducted in Chapters 3, 4 and 5, I reconsider Representational, Metaphysical and Modal Differences. According to a view that I propose: (a) Representational Difference entails (extreme) modal haecceitism for actual individuals but (extreme) modal antihaecceitism for possible individuals; (b) Metaphysical Difference entails metaphysical haecceitism (individualism) for actual individuals, but metaphysical antihaecceitism (generalism) for possible individuals; finally (c) Modal Difference entails existentialism: while there are singular and contingent possibilities involving actual individuals, all possibilities about possible individuals are general and necessary. In Chapter 6, I also explain the implications of those views for the various issues, including transworld identity, essentialism, or the modal status of modal space. Lastly, Chapter 7 overviews some semantic and metaphysical applications of Aristotelian ersatzism. I explain how it manages to accommodate Kripkean semantics and how it is able to account for the possibilities of indiscernibles, alien individuals and iterated modalities. I also address some possible objections to my proposal, including an issue of implicit representation and the Humphrey objection.
Vaidya, Anand and Dusko Prelevic (eds.), Epistemology of Modality and Philosophical Methodology, Routledge, 2022
A theory of what it is for a proposition to be metaphysical necessary should satisfy a number of desiderata. Among other things, it should account for the characteristic connections between metaphysical modality and various other philosophically important notions, and it should explain how it is possible for us to possess the modal knowledge we have. I will describe the links between modal concepts and three other concepts (possible worlds, counterfactuals, and essence) in section 1. It is tempting to try to exploit the connections between modality and these other notions to give an illuminating account of necessity. However, existing attempts to do so face significant limitations. I will draw on previous work (Kment 2014) to propose a theory of modality that can shed light on the conceptual connections (section 2). Finally, after discussing some preliminaries in section 3, I will argue (section 4) that the account outlined in section 2 also yields an attractive explanation of how modal knowledge is possible. 2 Not everyone agrees that Lewis's account is truly reductive.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.