Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
This paper deals with the relationship between legal responsibility and causation. I argue that legal responsibility is not necessarily rooted in causation. First, I show (in §1) that there are significant and independent non-causal form of responsibility that cannot be reduced to causal responsibility; second, in §2, I show that the very notion of causality is—lato sensu—not plainly descriptive. I will suggest that even causation is tied to evaluative elements.
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Online, 2001
Causal language is pervasive in the law, especially in those areas, such as contract law, tort law and criminal law, that deal with legal responsibility for the adverse consequences of voluntary and involuntary human interactions. Yet there are widely varying theories on the nature and role of causation in the law. At one extreme, the causal minimalists claim that causation plays little or no role in attributions of legal responsibility. At the opposite extreme, the causal maximalists claim that causation is the primary or sole determinant of legal responsibility. These divergent views are rooted in different conceptions of: (1) the nature or meaning of causation, (2) the relationship between causation and attributions of legal responsibility, and (3) the basic purposes of the relevant areas of law. Much of the disagreement and confusion stems from the ambiguous usages of causal language in the law, which follow the ambiguous usages of causal language in ordinary, non-legal discourse. In both areas, causal language is sometimes used in its primary sense to refer to the content and operation of the empirical laws of nature, but at other times it is used in a more restricted normative sense to signify that one of the contributing conditions has been identified as being more important than the other conditions, in relation to some particular purpose. The relevant purpose in the law is the attribution of legal responsibility for some consequence. Thus, in legal discourse, causal language is ambiguously employed to grapple not only with the empirical issue of causal contribution but also with the normative issue of legal responsibility. The failure to use language that clearly identifies and distinguishes these two issues has generated considerable disagreement and confusion over each issue and the nature of the relationship between them. Further disagreement and confusion have been generated by the difficulty of providing useful, comprehensive criteria for the resolution of each of these issues. The most widely used criterion for the empirical issue of causal contribution is the necessary-condition (conditio sine qua non) test. This test has been subjected to considerable criticism as being over-inclusive or under-inclusive or both, and as inviting or even requiring resort to normative policy issues to resolve what supposedly is a purely empirical issue. The deficiencies of the necessary-condition test, coupled with the difficulties encountered in trying to devise a useful alternative test that does not beg the question, have led many to conclude that there is no purely empirical concept of causation, and that there is thus no more than a minimal role for causation in the attribution of legal responsibility. This causal-minimalist position has been especially attractive to the legal economists and the critical legal scholars, since it undermines the traditional conception of the law as an instrument of interactive justice, whereby everyone is required to avoid causing injury to the persons and property of others through interactions that fail to respect properly those others’ equal dignity and autonomy. The traditional conception, with its focus on individual autonomy, rights and causation, is inconsistent with the social-welfare maximizing theories of the legal economists and the anti-liberal, deconstructionist programme of the critical legal scholars. The members of each causal-minimalist group therefore argue that the concept of causation should be: (a) jettisoned entirely and replaced by direct resort to the social policy goals which they believe do or should determine the ultimate incidence and extent of legal responsibility; (b) redefined as being reducible to those social policy goals; or (c) retained as useful rhetoric that can be manipulated to achieve or camouflage the pursuit of those social policy goals.
Chicago-Kent} Law Review, 2016
Law & Society: Public Law - Crime, 2016
Causation plays an essential role in attributions of legal responsibility. However, considerable confusion has been generated in philosophy, law and economics by the use of causal language to refer not merely to causation in its basic (actual/factual/natural) sense, which refers to the operation of the laws of nature, but also to the quite different normative issue of appropriate legal responsibility. To reduce such confusion, we argue that causal language in these disciplines should be used to refer solely to causation in its basic sense. While it is often said that the law need not and should not concern itself with philosophical analyses of causation, we demonstrate that this is incorrect with respect to causation in its basic sense. After surveying the philosophical foundations of the modern analyses of causation, we discuss the inadequacy of the counterfactual strong necessity (sine qua non, but-for) criterion for a condition to be a cause in a specific instance, which is domin...
Philosophy Compass, 2007
In this article I examine the relation between causation and moral responsibility. I distinguish four possible views about that relation. One is the standard view: the view that an agent's moral responsibility for an outcome requires, and is grounded in, the agent's causal responsibility for it. I discuss several challenges to the standard view, which motivate the three remaining views. The final viewthe view I argue for -is that causation is the vehicle of transmission of moral responsibility. According to this view, although moral responsibility does not require causation, causation still grounds moral responsibility.
CTLA Forum, 2025
In part 1 of this article, published in the CTLA Forum Winter 2025 at pages 18-22, 40-45, I discuss the substantial confusion regarding the required elements for tort liability caused by the Connecticut courts’ and the first and second Restatements’ lumping together the actual causation and scope of liability elements under the question-begging and misleading phrases “substantial factor,” “legal cause” and “proximate cause.” I discuss the initial rejection by the Connecticut courts of the foreseeable consequences (“harm matches the risk” = harm risked”) limitation on the scope of liability as being unstable, unjust and inconsistent with the cases and their implicit adoption, instead, of the normatively more attractive and descriptively more comprehensive “harm results from the risk” (“risk playout”) limitation. I discuss the first and second Restatements’ adoption of the harm-risked limitation as a limitation on duty and their attempt to make it more consistent with the cases by excluding significant aspects of the foreseeable risks, making several significant exceptions, and employing explanations that gut the limitation by using hindsight rather than foresight. I note that many of the comments in the first and second Restatements employ risk playout language rather than harm-risked language, without apparently being aware of the significant difference between these two formulations. I also discuss the Restatement Third’s correction of many of the defects in the first and second Restatements. It abandons use of the “substantial factor,” “proximate cause” and “legal cause” terminology and instead clearly distinguishes the “factual causation” issue from the “scope of liability” issue. It adopts (except for the deficient blackletter in section 27) the proper NESS analysis as the comprehensive test of factual causation. It adopts Andrews’ position in Palsgraf that a duty is owed to everyone to exercise reasonable care when engaging in conduct that creates foreseeable risks to others, subject to categorical principle-or-policy-based limits in specific types of situations. It adopts the risk-playout limitation on the scope of liability in place of the previously adopted harm-risked limitation on duty, although it also does not seem to recognize the significant difference between the two limitations. It properly recognizes, as distinct limitations on the scope of liability, the “no worse off” and “trivial contribution” limitations. In part 2, forthcoming in the Spring 2025 CTLA Forum, I discuss the arguments in all three Restatements, which are implemented in the Third Restatement, that the superseding cause limitation can and should be absorbed and replaced by the harm-risked limitation, despite the courts’ continued regular use of the former limitation and the Third Restatement’s having replaced the latter limitation with the risk playout limitation. The Restatements fail to note the significant differences in the proper formulation and application of each limitation. The Restatement Third argues that the primary/sole rationale for the superseding cause limitation was mitigation of the inequitable allocation of liability among multiple responsible parties, which supposedly is no longer a concern given the modern practice of using comparative responsibility principles to allocate liability between plaintiffs and defendants and among defendants. Both parts of this argument are defective. First, the superseding cause limitation has never been based on a concern about inequitable apportionment of liability among multiple responsible parties in the absence of modern apportionment rules, but rather a concern that a defendant should not be deemed responsible at all for a harm that occurred only because of some highly unexpected or extraordinary conduct or event for which it would not be just to hold her responsible. Second, elimination of the superseding cause limitation would not change existing apportionment rules, none of which provide for comprehensive pure comparative responsibility and most of which would continue, in the absence of the superseding cause limitation, to impose substantial and even full legal responsibility on an actor for a harm that would not have occurred if not for the intervention of some highly unexpected or extraordinary conduct or event for which he should not justly be held responsible.
European Scientific Journal, 2014
This article deals with the conception of causation in legal discourse. Authors firstly examine causation in the scientific, philosophical and common-sense discourse. Does it make sense to use general causal terms when examining causality in law? We can ask whether legal causality isn´t only artificial construct, legal fiction of a causal relationship. Some authors claim that legal causation is not essentially a causation in the true common sense and thus only a pragmatic political decision regarding the application of distributive and corrective justice, and economic evaluation of benefits in society, others on the contrary point out that causality in law as such is equal to its common everyday use or even in the scientific sense. What are the criteria in the legal sense that lead us to judge that certain event causes harm? Which issues relevant to philosophical discourse may be in legal discourse ignored as irrelevant? The authors show the necessary connection between terms causality in different branches although they conclude that causality is pluralistic concept. The issue of this article is to find out solution for causal connection in particular paradigmatic cases and set up some causal formulas that could be used in legal practice.
Chicago-Kent} Law Review, 1987
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2014
This paper offers a logical analysis of two cases where legal responsibility may emerge for the acts of others: (a) reflex responsibility, and (b) responsibility in the negotiorum gestio doctrine. The current contribution works within a fresh multi-modal system where the new operators are introduced for denoting intentions and actions in the interest of other agents, and the objectively ideal sets of actions for agents.
Calabresi often lamented that insufficient consideration had been given in the legal and economic literature to the idea of distributing an accident loss among a faultless tortfeasor and an innocent victim on the basis of the relative causal contribution of the parties to the loss. This criterion of apportionment of liability, which Calabresi calls comparative causation, is the object of this paper. We present a brief intellectual history of the principle of comparative causation, and provide a positive economic model that explains the rise and fall of this criterion of liability in historical and contemporary societies. In order to identify the structural features of this standard, we consider how a rule of comparative causation would perform in the absence of other liability rules, when applied as a general and sole basis of liability. The positive economic model of comparative causation brings to light some interesting features of the rule, but also unveils the limits of such cri...
According to our view, inferential approaches to legal liability (including cases of pre-emption), embedded in a dialogical framework yield a quite intuitive implementation of Armgardt's proposal to respond to Moore's (2010) study of cases of causal overdetermination in Law, provided the deployment of a fully interpreted language as the one of Martin-Löf's (1984) Constructive Type Theory is casted in a dialogical framework-rather than in a possible-world one-, whereby (1) hypothetical judgements (involving non-actualized tokens) can be explicitly distinguished from categorical conditional judgements, (2) tokens of actions can be introduced as explicit denizens of the object-language, (3) actual harm/tort events are analysed as tokens dependent upon tokens of their (putative) causes-i.e. as (multi) functions over tokens of their causes, (4) tokens of actions can be "enriched" with a timing function. The paper will be divided in two main parts.. The first one follows Armgardt's strategy to start by establishing collective Liability and proceed afterwards with the identification of individual Liability. The second main part, proposes a framework for the attribution of individual responsibility with regard to the determination of individual Causation. This second way is led by the rationale that legally liable is the one who caused the damage, individually or in association with others.
Legal, Moral, and Metaphysical Truths: The Philosophy of Michael S. Moore, 2016
This paper was prepared for a festschrift in honor of Michael Moore published by Oxford University Press. Moore's magnum opus, Causation and Responsibility, amply demonstrates his encyclopedic knowledge of the relevant sources in law and philosophy and his analytical skill. Much can be learned from careful, critical reading. However, I argue, Moore relies too much on intuition -- more specifically, his own -- in developing his account of causation and its pervasive and (he claims) dominant role in attributions of legal responsibility. Focusing on the NESS account that I have elaborated, he rejects 'generalist' accounts of causation, which analyze singular instances of causation as instantiations of causal (natural) laws, instead opting for a 'primitivist singularist' account, according to which we simply recognize causation when we see it in each particular instance without any even implicit reference to causal laws or any other 'reductionist' test. He erroneously treats the 'substantial factor' criterion in the first and second Restatements of Torts (which is properly strongly criticized and rejected in the third Restatement) as being such a primitivist singularist account. In addition, he seeks to replace all of the traditional normative limitations on legal responsibility with a supposed causal analysis, based on the 'scalarity' of causation.Yet, Moore believes, intuitions come into conflict with metaphysics when considering omissions or other absences as causes, which is routinely assumed to be true in law and life but which Moore insists is fundamentally erroneous from a metaphysical standpoint. His insistence on this point, while admirable from an intellectual integrity standpoint, completely undermines the fundamental premise of his book -- that causation is the pervasive and dominant determinant of legal responsibility -- since omissions/absences are part of every causal chain involving human action and many not involving human action. In this paper, I defend a specific ';generalist' account of causation (the NESS account) and criticize Moore's primitivist singularist account. Along the way, I address a number of issues regarding causation and legal responsibility, including the metaphysical basis for treating omissions as causes.
The Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 2004
herever there is scarcity of resources in relation to human demand, the possibility of conflict arises. The solution to such conflict is the assignment of private property rights-rights of exclusive control. All scarce resources must be owned privately in order to avoid otherwise inescapable conflicts. However, while the assignment of private property rights makes conflict-free interaction possible, it does not assure it. The possibility of property rights violations exists, and if there are violations, then there must be rights of self-defense and punishment as well as liability on the part of a wrongdoer (Hoppe 1987 and 1993). All this holds true regardless of how and to whom such rights are assigned and who accordingly is or is not considered aggressor or victim in any given case. We still remain in the realm of "positive" legal analysis when we consider what might be called a praxeological requirement of any system of assigning property rights. In order to make conflict-free interaction possible, every such system must take into account the fact that man does and must act. In other words, it must be an "operational" system. To accomplish this, based on the system adopted, human actors must be able to determine ex ante, at any moment in time, what they are and are not permitted to do. In order to determine this, there need be some "objective" borders, signs, and indicators of ownership and property as well as of wrongful invasion of said ownership and property. Similarly, when considering a case ex post, judges must have "objective" criteria of property and aggression to make a determination for or against a plaintiff.
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 2013
The article analyses and reconstructs a broad idea of legal responsibility which underlies and normatively links tort law with the law of unjustified enrichment. The article's central proposition is that responsibility for damage caused and enrichment-responsibility are closely interrelated. Both aspects of obligations are equally an expression of corrective justice, and ultimately serve to protect the civil rights of citizens. It is shown that the idea of civil equality and the principle against unjustified enrichment require citizens to assume responsibility not only for the consequences of their misbehaviour, but also for the consequences of lawful actions that non-reciprocally endanger the rights of others. This can be seen particularly clearly in cases of necessity like Vincent v Lake Erie. Under current law, those cases fall in between the categories of unjustified enrichment and wrongs; in most legal systems, they are therefore regarded as particularly hard cases. Nevertheless, the liability of a person lawfully causing damage in a situation of necessity exemplifies the idea of legal responsibility, and thus helps in better understanding the law of non-contractual obligations. Methodologically, the article combines historical arguments derived from the late scholastic theory of restitution with a comparative analysis of Western legal systems and contemporary private law theory. This approach is designed to overcome the conceptual boundaries of national private laws on both sides of the English Channel; it may help to address difficult legal problems more appropriately.
Philosophia, 2013
In discussions of moral responsibility for collectively produced effects, it is not uncommon to assume that we have to abandon the view that causal involvement is a necessary condition for individual co-responsibility. In general, considerations of cases where there is "a mismatch between the wrong a group commits and the apparent causal contributions for which we can hold individuals responsible" motivate this move. According to Brian Lawson, "solving this problem requires an approach that deemphasizes the importance of causal contributions". Christopher Kutz's theory of complicitious accountability in Complicity from 2000 is probably the most well-known approach of that kind. Standard examples are supposed to illustrate mismatches of three different kinds: an agent may be morally coresponsible for an event to a high degree even if her causal contribution to that event is a) very small, b) imperceptible, or c) non-existent (in overdetermination cases). From such examples, Kutz and others conclude that principles of complicitious accountability cannot include a condition of causal involvement. In the present paper, I defend the causal involvement condition for co-responsibility. These are my lines of argument: First, overdetermination cases can be accommodated within a theory of coresponsibility without giving up the causality condition. Kutz and others oversimplify the relation between counterfactual dependence and causation, and they overlook the possibility that causal relations other than marginal contribution could be morally relevant. Second, harmful effects are sometimes overdetermined by noncollective sets of acts. Over-farming, or the greenhouse effect, might be cases of that kind. In such cases, there need not be any formal organization, any unifying intentions, or any other noncausal criterion of membership available. If we give up the causal condition for coresponsibility it will be impossible to delimit the morally relevant set of acts related to those harms. Since we sometimes find it fair to blame people for such harms, we must question the argument from overdetermination.
Extended abstract for my talk at the Centre Léon Robin (CNRS, Université de Paris IV -Sorbonne) PRC Fapesp/CNRS "PATHOS. La doctrine aristotélicienne des émotions" ,23 May 2019 It attempts to link and summarize the joint work on dialectical legal reasoing with natural and deontic necessity. it is based on the book in print and two other papers, but i added some new reflections it is nevertheless only an abstract. However, here and there, informed by recent discussions with Hassan Tahiri and Walter E. Young I added some new remarks and (initial) reflections on how to embed the subject of the papers (the parallelism between natural and deontic necessitation) in the dialectical framework of the theory of the occasioning factor (the Islamic counterpart to notion of ratio legis of Roman Law), the main subject of the book. C
Legal Theory, 2009
This paper takes it as a premise that a distinction between matters of fact and of law is important in the causal inquiry. But it argues that separating factual and legal causation as different elements of liability is not the best way to implement the fact/law distinction. It is partly a legal question what counts as a cause-in-fact; and certain liability-limiting doctrines under the umbrella of “legal causation” depend on the application of factual-causal concepts. The contrastive account of factual causation proposed in this paper improves matters. This account more clearly distinguishes matters of fact from matters of law within the cause-in-fact inquiry. It also extends the scope of cause-in-fact to answer some questions currently answered by certain doctrines of legal causation – doctrines which, it is argued, are more naturally seen as applications of our ordinary causal concept than as non-causal liability-limiting devices.
International Review of Law and Economics, 2004
This paper considers alternative approaches to dealing with causal uncertainty in strict liability tort regimes. Beginning from the philosophical literature on causing, a distinction is made between the scientific idea of causality and the legal idea of causation. This distinction is generalized to a context of causal uncertainty and associated probabilities are constructed. It is shown that a rule of proportional liability whereby the tortfeasor pays damages in proportion to the probability in causation of them having caused the damage would be socially efficient. This contrasts with the implied use of the probability in causality by the courts and in the law and economics literature on causal uncertainty.
2011
Abstract: This article is part of a symposium on Michael Moore's Causation and Responsibility. In Causation and Responsibility, Moore adopts a scalar approach to factual causation, with counterfactual dependency serving as an independent desert basis. Moore's theory of causation does not include proximate causation. The problem with Moore's argument is that the problems with which proximate causation dealt-how and when to limit cause in fact-remain unresolved.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.