Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2019, Proceedings of the 2019 Conference of the International Fuzzy Systems Association and the European Society for Fuzzy Logic and Technology (EUSFLAT 2019)
Convexity of preferences is a canonical assumption in economic theory. In this paper we consider a generalized definition of convex preferences that relies on the abstract notion of convex space.
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
Studia Universitatis „Vasile Goldis” Arad – Economics Series
The concept of convexity plays an important role in the study of economics and consumer theory. For the most part, such studies have been conducted on the assumption that consumer preferences are a binary relation that is complete, reflexive and transitive on the set X of consumption choices. However, each consumer is a biological being with multidimensional physiological needs so that possible consumptions from different dimensions cannot be compared by using preferences. By removing that unrealistic assumption, this paper examines how the various concepts of convex preferences and relevant properties can be re-established. We derive a series of 10 formal propositions and construct 6 examples to show that (a) a weighted combination of two possible consumptions is not necessarily comparable with any of the consumptions; (b) not every convergent sequence of a consumer’s preferred consumptions asymptotically preserves that consumer’s preference preordering; (c) not all preferences sat...
Russell and S. Chattopadhyay for stimulating discussions. I also thank participants at the International Conference on Advances in Convex Analysis and Global Optimization in Samos and at a seminar at the University of Nottingham for their comments. I am also grateful for the financial support by Spanish Ministry of Sciences and Technology. Project No. BEC2002-03097 and by the Instituto Valenciano de Investigaciones Economicas.
Convexity plays a crucial role in proving the existence of various equilibria in cooperative and noncooperative game theories. While convex analysis on vector spaces has brought a plenty of fruitful results to optimization theory and its application to economics and game theory, it is apparent that standard convex analysis is inadequate to deal with topological spaces which lack a vector space structure. In particular, not enough investigation has been made concerning convexity in æ-fields of measure spaces. In this paper we propose a convex-like structure in a nonatomic finite mea- sure space. We first introduce convex combinations of measurable sets, and quasi-concave and concave functions on a Borel æ-field and prove Jensen's in- equalities, which conform with the standard definitions results in convex anal- ysis. We then introduce the convexity of preference relations on the Borel æ- field and show that a utility function representing the convex preference rela- tion is quas...
Journal of Mathematical Economics, 1986
Mathematical Social Sciences, 1995
We consider a class of relations which includes irreflexive preference relations and interdependent preferences. For this class, we obtain necessary and sufficient conditions for representation of the relation by two numerical functions in the sense of a ~ x if and only if u(a) < vex).
Journal of Mathematical Economics, 2000
We characterize the existence of a nonnegative, sublinear and continuous order-preserving function for a not necessarily complete preorder on a real convex cone in an arbitrary topological real vector space. As a corollary of the main result, we present necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of such an order-preserving function for a complete preorder.
Journal of Economic Theory, 2008
We provide a general impossibility theorem on the aggregation of preferences under uncertainty. We axiomatize in the Anscombe-Aumann setting a wide class of preferences, called rank-dependent additive preferences that includes most known models of decision under uncertainty as well as state-dependent versions of these models. We prove that aggregation is possible and necessarily linear if and only if (society's) preferences are uncertainty neutral. The latter means that society cannot have a non-neutral attitude toward uncertainty on a subclass of acts. A corollary to our theorem is that it is not possible to aggregate multiple prior agents, even when they all have the same set of priors. A number of extensions are considered.
In this paper we are concerned with numerical representation of preferences over bundles. Specifically, we provide an axiomatic characterization of preferences that have a numerical representation that look similar to a concave function defined on a convex set. We call such preferences concave. We also show that the concept of a super-gradient is inherent to rational choice. We discuss additively separable preferences and their axiomatization due to Fishburn (1970) since they are an important example of concave preferences. Using the same methods that we use to prove earlier results we show that the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics holds for combinatorial assignment problems.
2015
We consider a decision maker that holds multiple preferences simultaneously, each with different strengths described by a probability distribution. Faced with a subset of available alternatives, the preferences held by the individual can be in conflict. Choice results from an aggregation of these preferences. We assume that the aggregation method is monotonic: improvements in the position of alternative x cannot displace x if it were originally the choice. We show that choices made in this manner can be represented by context-dependent utility functions that are monotonic with respect to a measure of the strength of each alternative among those available. Using this representation we show that any generic monotonic rule can generate an arbitrary choice function as we vary the distribution of preferences. Domain restrictions on the set of preferences (e.g. dual motivation models) or consistency restrictions on the aggregator across choice sets reduce the set of admissible behaviors. Applications to positive models of individual decision making with context effects and social choice are discussed.
Arthaniti: Journal Of Economic Theory And Practice, 2018
In this paper, we show that there does not exist any triple acyclic preference aggregation rule that satisfies Majority property, weak Pareto criterion and a version of a property due to Alan Taylor. We also show that there are non-dictatorial preference aggregation rules and in particular non-dictatorial social welfare functions which satisfy the weak Pareto criterion and Taylor's Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives. Further, we are able to obtain analogous results for preference aggregation functionals by suitably adjusting the desired properties to fit into a framework which uses individual utility functions rather than individual preference orderings. Our final result is a modest generalisation of Sen's version of Arrow's impossibility theorem which is shown to hold under our mild domain restriction.
Economic Theory Bulletin, 2018
We construct a complete space of smooth strictly convex preference relations defined over physical commodities and monetary transfers. This construction extends the classical one by assuming that preferences are monotone in transfers, but not necessarily in all commodities. We thereby provide a natural framework to perform genericity analyses in situations involving inventory costs or decisions under risk. The space of preferences we construct is contractible, which allows for a natural aggregation procedure in collective decision situations.
2005
We provide a general theorem on the aggregation of preferences under uncertainty. We study, in the Anscombe-Aumann setting a wide class of preferences, that includes most known models of decision under uncertainty (and state-dependent versions of these models). We prove that aggregation is possible and necessarily linear if (society's) preferences are "smooth". The latter means that society cannot have a non-neutral attitude towards uncertainty on a subclass of acts. A corollary to our theorem is that it is not possible to aggregate maxmin expected utility maximizers, even when they all have the same set of priors. We show that dropping a weak notion of monotonicity on society's preferences allows one to restore the possibility of aggregation of non-smooth preferences.
Journal of Mathematical Economics, 1987
It is shown that if a consumer's preference ordering is strictly convex and is representable by means of a concave, twice continuously differentiable utility function, then the partial derivative of a demanded commodity with respect to its price is bounded from above in a neighborhood of a price vector at which the demand fails to be differentiable.
Working paper series (RGEA), 2008
We consider a continuum of commodities represented by a real interval or, more generally, by a convex set K of any Euclidean space. A consumption plan is a real function defined on the set of commodities K. We show that strictly monotonic preferences on the set of consumption plans always exist. However, they are not representable by utility functions. Moreover, if we consider a consumption set with topological structure, as the positive cone of the Banach space of bounded functions on K, we show that continuous preferences cannot be strictly monotonic.
Order, 2009
We find conditions on the order on subsets of a finite set which are necessary and sufficient for the relative ranking of any two subsets in this order to be determined by their extreme elements relative to an abstract convex geometry. It turns out that this question is closely related to the rationalisability of path independent choice functions by hyper-relations.
Social Choice and Welfare, 1999
An Excess-Voting Function relative to a pro®le p assigns to each pair of alternatives xY y, the number of voters who prefer x to y minus the number of voters who prefer y to x. It is shown that any non-binary separable Excess-Voting Function can be achieved from a preferences pro®le when individuals are endowed with separable preferences. This result is an extension of Hollard and Le Breton (1996). Soc Choice Welfare (1999) 16: 159±167 Many thanks are due to Jean-FrancË ois Laslier and to two referees for their valuable remarks to improve this paper. I would like to thank Basudeb Chaudhuri for his careful reading.
Springer eBooks, 2006
A direct construction of concave utility functions representing convex preferences on finite sets is presented. An alternative construction in which at first directions of supergradients ("prices") are found, and then utility levels and lengths of those supergradients are computed, is exhibited as well. The concept of a least concave utility function is problematic in this context.
Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 2003
We study the topological properties of aggregation maps combining individuals' preferences over n alternatives, with preference expressed by a real-valued, n-dimensional utility vector u defined on an interval scale. Since any such utility vector is specified only up to arbitrary affine transformations, the space of utility vectors R n may be partitioned into equivalence classes of the form fau þ b1 j aAR þ 0 ; bARg: The quotient space, denoted T; is shown to be the union of the n À 2-dimensional sphere S ¼ S nÀ2 with the singleton f0g; which corresponds to indifference or null preference. The topology of T is non-Hausdorff, placing it outside the scope of most existing theory (e.g., J. Econom. Theory 31 (1983) 68). We then investigate the existence and nature of continuous aggregation maps under the four scenarios of allowing or disallowing null preference both in individual and in social choice, i.e. maps f : P Â ? Â P-Q with P; QAfT; Sg: We show that there exist continuous, anonymous, unanimous aggregation maps iff the outcome space includes the null point ðQ ¼ TÞ; and provide a simple well-behaved example for the case f : S Â ? Â S-T: Similar examples exist for f : T Â ? Â T-T; but these and all other maps have a property of always either over-or under-allocating influence to each voter (in a specific manner). We conclude that there exist acceptable aggregation rules if and only if null preference is allowed for the society but not for the individual. r
Mathematical Social Sciences, 1999
A main aim of this paper is to make connections between two well-but up to now independently-developed theories, the theory of choice functions and the theory of closure operators. It is shown that the classes of ordinally rationalizable and path independent choice functions are related to the classes of distributive and anti-exchange closures.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.