Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
Saul Kripke's study of the truth conditions for modal and for subjunctive conditional statements is meant to validate essentialism. To this end he develops his rigid theory of rigid designators, and he enlists the service of normal intuition. Even were his argument valid, his conclusion is unacceptable since language and intuition are flexible and open-ended, and since essentialist expressions ordinarily serve as mere metaphors.
The goal of the present paper is to show how Saul Kripke´s modal logic and semantics uses the concept of essential property, and that this entails weaknesses in his theory as presented in Naming and Necessity, for there are classes of referring expressions Kripke's semantics cannot handle, e.g., to limited classes of artifacts. A functionalist approach will resolve these difficulties, and return us to the descriptivist theory of names. This paper´s content is novel because it analyzes Kripke´s taxonomic classification of names and other referring expressions under a functionalist approximation.
Filosofska Dumka, 2022
The article discusses Saul Kripke's criticisms of the account of the reference of general names he called "descriptivism" and the considerations he advanced in favour of his own essentialist causal-historical account of the reference of natural kind terms. The alternative of conceptualism versus essentialism about the reference of general terms is explained in details. The case is made that most of the intuitions on which Kripke based his arguments are highly controversial, and the main examples he used to explain and support his views (such as examples of whales and fish, water and H20, gold, tigers, and unicorns) do not constitute a clear case for the preference of essentialism over conceptualism. Moreover, these examples can be modified in such ways that in the perspective of these modifications, Kripke's essentialist construal turns out to be far-fetched and implausible, whereas a form of conceptualism (the cluster theory of reference) is tenable.
Philosophy, 2006
... semantic contents of the claims that use of the modal operators enables us to make. ... (On a de re modalist view there can be necessary truths in which de re modality is ... will concern abstract entities or they will be inferential principles for reasoning with de re modal notions.) Thus ...
2021
Kripke’s Naming and Necessity (1980), based on his lectures at Princeton University in 1970, challenges the Kant’s doctrine of a priori, a posteriori, necessity, and contingency. Its theses problematize the Kantian point of view and reintroduce the possibility of metaphysics inquiries in the philosophical field. This article tries to show that the distinction between metaphysics and epistemology is Kripke’s main strategy for sustaining the existence of necessary a posteriori judgments and contingent a priori judgments. However, this distinction is based on a misunderstanding of Kant’s objective epistemology and overlooks Kant’s criticisms of the metaphysics’ claim to know the world itself. Besides, this text defends that the distinction between metaphysics and epistemology has serious consequences that can restrict or even deny some epistemological or metaphysical claims. If a priori judgments are not automatically necessary, what is the basis of mathematics? How can the concept of ...
In "Theoria", 88, pp. 278-295, 2022
In this paper, I try to outline what I take to be Naming and Necessity's fundamental legacy to my generation and those that follow, and the new perspectives it has opened up for twentyfirst century philosophy. The discussion is subdivided into three sections, concerning respectively philosophy of language, metaphysics, and metaphilosophy. The general unifying theme is that Naming and Necessity is helping philosophy to recover a Golden Age, by freeing it from the strictures coming from the empiricist and Kantian traditions and reconnecting it to the world and the objects that populate it. Because of this, in the concluding paragraph I tentatively suggest that Kripke's philosophy may be seen as a sui generis form of naturalism.
Philosophical Studies, 1993
Of what use is sense to semantics? A standard answer has been that sense provides the key to an account of opaque constructions, such as it's necessary that S and Michael believes that T. Many would say this answer has been thoroughly discredited. Kripke and Kaplan's arguments, that necessity is not a property of Fregean sense, are widely seen as conclusive. Russellians and Millians have laid siege to the idea that to ascribe a belief is to talk about sense. Though few have embraced the extremes of direct reference, many have come to agree that the orthodox Fregean's idea-a belief ascription implies a similarity in way of thinking, between ascriber and ascribee-simply doesn't get the facts right) Will sense go the way of Basic Law Vb? The second half of Forbes' Languages of Possibility, coupled with several of his recent papers, gives a sustained defense of the importance of sense for semantics. 2 While Forbes' account is at points reformed, not orthodox, it aspires to be recognizably Fregean. It seems to me the best sustained contemporary defense of Frege's views in philosophical semantics. But it is not, I think, entirely successful. In this essay, I present the outlines of Forbes' account of the semantics of necessity, of propositional attitudes, and of their intersection in (putative) examples of a priori yet contingent knowledge. In each case I raise objections to Forbes' account. The account of necessity, I argue, is either unFregean or unsuccessful. The account of attitudes, I will suggest, is Fregean and not successful. And the account of the contingent a priori, I think, cannot be accepted as it stands. 1. THE BEARER OF TRUTH, THE BEARER OF NECESSITY, AND THE OBJECT OF BELIEF In Naming and Necessity, Kripke assumes that the sense of a proper name is usually that of a definite description contingently true of the
After a brief review of the notions of necessity and a priority, this paper scrutinizes Kripke's arguments for supposedly contingent a priori propositions and necessary a posteriori propositions involving proper names, and reaches a negative conclusion, i.e. there are no such propositions, or at least the propositions Kripke gives as examples are not such propositions. All of us, including Kripke himself, still have to face the old question raised by Hume, i.e. how can we justify the necessity and universality of general statements on the basis of sensory or empirical evidence?
We discuss Saul Kripke's seminal 1963 paper 'Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic', and sketch subsequent developments in modal logic with a view to their general logical thrust.
Nous, 2019
Kripke (1980) hypothesizes a link between rigidity and scope: a singular term is rigid over a space S of possibilities just in case it is scopeless with respect to modals that quantify over S. Kripke's hypothesis works well when we consider the interaction of singular terms with metaphysical modals, but runs into trouble when we consider the interaction of singular terms with epistemic modals. After describing the trouble in detail, and considering one non-solution to it, I develop a novel version of dynamic semantics that resolves the problem.
2007
... Re-Reading: Saul A.. Kripke, 'Naming and Necessity'. Finn Spicer. Philosophical Papers. ISSN: 0556-8641. Postal address: PO Box 377, Grahamstown, South Africa, 6140 Phone: +27(46) 622 9698 Fax: +27(0)46 622 9550 E-mail: [email protected].
Erkenntnis, 1994
2021
Prior to Kripke's seminal work on the semantics of modal logic, McKinsey offered an alternative interpretation of the necessity operator, inspired by the Bolzano-Tarski notion of logical truth. According to this interpretation, 'it is necessary that A' is true just in case every sentence with the same logical form as A is true. In our paper, we investigate this interpretation of the modal operator, resolving some technical questions, and relating it to the logical interpretation of modality and some views in modal metaphysics. In particular, we present an hitherto unpublished solution to problems 41 and 42 from Friedman's 102 problems, which uses a different method of proof from the solution presented in the paper of Tadeusz Prucnal.
Kripke asks why this should seem surprising (Kripke, 394). Kripke states that in interpreting this argument, he is using a weak interpretation of 'necessity:'A statement is necessary when, if the objects mentioned in the statement exist, then the statement would be true (Kripke, 394). Kripke is not claiming the sort of necessity that says something must necessarily exist. Instead, he is interested in looking at what could be said about an object if that object exists (Kripke, 395).
Logos & episteme, 2024
One of Kripke's innovations concerning the philosophy of language is the doctrine that the truth of some metaphysically necessary propositions is only known a posteriori. The typical example he gives is the identity statement consists of two different proper names that refer to the same referent, like "Hesperus = Phosphorus". By metaphysically necessary he means that the proposition is true in all possible worlds and by a posteriori knowledge he means that its truth is known by experiment or investigation. Some philosophers have given arguments against Kripke's doctrine and claimed that such propositions can, also, be known a priori. In this paper, I will defend Kripke's view by showing that his approach to the issue is linguistic not metaphysical, opposite to his critics.
Filosofska Dumka, 2020
The article discusses Saul Kripke’s influential theories of a posteriori necessary truths and natural kinds. With respect to the statements of identity involving proper names, it is argued that although their truth is a posteriori and necessary in the specific sense of counterfactual invariance, this is of no significance for substantial philosophical issues beyond the philosophy of language, because this counterfactual invariance is a trivial consequence of the use of proper names as rigid designators. The case is made that the expansion of the realm of necessary a posteriori truths to the statements of theoretical identity that involve “natural kind terms”, as well as the Kripkean essentialist theory of natural kinds, has no weighty argumentative support and fits badly both with science and language practice. This sets the stage for the development of an appropriately sophisticated «descriptivist» account of meaning and reference that would be better suited for a widened range of Kripke-Putnam style thought experiments. The general outlines of such a descriptivist account are provided.
Principia: an international journal of epistemology
http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2016v20n1p1In ‘Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic’, Kripke articulates his project in the discourse of “possible worlds”. There has been much philosophical discussion of whether endorsement of the Kripke semantics brings ontological commitment to possible worlds. However, that discussion is less than satisfactory because it has been conducted without the necessary investigation of the surrounding philosophical issues that are raised by the Kripke semantics. My aim in this paper is to map out the surrounding territory and to commence that investigation. Among the surrounding issues, and my attitudes to them, are these: (1) the potential of the standard distinction between pure and impure versions of the semantic theory has been under-exploited; (2) there has been under-estimation of what is achieved by the pure semantic theory alone; (3) there is a methodological imperative to co-ordinate a clear conception of the purposes of the impure theor...
Theoria, 2012
This article systematically challenges Kripke's modal argument and Soames's defence of this argument by arguing that, just like descriptions, names can take narrow or wide scopes over modalities, and that there is a big difference between the wide scope reading and the narrow scope reading of a modal sentence with a name. Its final conclusions are that all of Kripke's and Soames's arguments are untenable due to some fallacies or mistakes; names are not "rigid designators"; if there were rigid designators, description(s) could be rigidified to refer fixedly to objects; so names cannot be distinguished in this way from the corresponding descriptions. A descriptivist account of names is still correct; and there is no justification for Kripke's theory of rigid designation and its consequences.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.