Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2003, Nietzsche and the German Tradition
This essay examines cultural attitudes to Nietzsche in the German Democratic Republic (GDR), which appeared to be changing in the mid- to late 1980s, after almost forty years of deliberate, officially sanctioned neglect of the thinker. Nietzsche's voice had been effectively silenced in the GDR and his manuscripts carefully guarded. While it was not impossible to gain access to Nietzsche's manuscripts, scholars had to tackle a bureaucratic assault course in order to reach them. Reception of Nietzsche in the GDR tended to be limited and negative. There was nothing even resembling an open discussion in the GDR of Nietzsche and his legacies before 1986, and the first Nietzsche monograph to be published there did not appear until 1989. Discussions of Nietzsche in the GDR were rare, and they tended to focus only on his alleged role in paving the way for National Socialism and/or bourgeois imperialism. The depth and intensity of official hostility to Nietzsche in the GDR can be traced, in part, to the founding ideas and self-understanding of that state. Its claims to legitimacy were based on two closely related ideas. The first was a Marxist-Leninist interpretation of historical development, according to which the GDR was the culmination of progressive ('zukunftsweisend') developments in German history. The second was the antifascist struggle of 1933-1945, which provided the GDR with its immediate raison d’être. The presence of the victorious Red Army on German soil, the sacrifices of the Soviet people in repelling the fascist invader, and the martyrdom of German antifascists in the Third Reich appeared to provide compelling evidence for both these claims to legitimacy. There was no room for Nietzsche in the ‘first antifascist state on German soil’, as his writings were perceived (and not only by communists) to have been an important underpinning of National Socialism. A debate in 1986-87 in the GDR journal *Sinn und Form* on opening up Nietzsche's work to public debate seemed to be part of a cultural thaw in East Germany. This debate in the GDR was a curiously muted and oblique version of a process which, by 1987, was already well underway in Mikhail Gorbachev's Soviet Union: glasnost. In the event, in the GDR context it was too little, too late.
The Review of Politics, 1995
In his later books Nietzsche repeatedly complains that philosophers have no sense of history. On a more modest level and with gentler and more respectful remonstrance, Christian J. Emden makes a similar claim. Surveying recent discussions of Nietzsche's political thought in English, he remarks that they show little awareness of the political context in which Nietzsche lived and to which his views responded. It should not be forgotten that Nietzsche lived through several of the more tumultuous turning points in German history: the Revolution of 1848, the Austro-Prussian War, the Franco-Prussian War, the creation of the new German state, and the subsequent economic boom, which brought in its train panics and a search for scapegoats.
Choice Reviews Online, 2009
Friedrich Nietzsche and the Politics of History Christian J. Emden Frontmatter More information A natural history of moral communities 237 Sovereign individuals and the ethic of responsibility 248 The task of genealogy 260 "To translate humanity back into nature" 269 6 The idea of Europe and the limits of genealogy 286 "The creation of the European individual" 287 Beyond the modern nation state 299 Political realities in Imperial Germany 308 Modernity and the limits of genealogy 316 Bibliography 324 Index 366 Contents x
Friedrich Nietzsche’s critique of values offers an important account of contemporary culture. In this essay I will examine Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals and Beyond Good and Evil, drawing out Nietzsche’s revaluation of values. This essay is intended to demonstrate the ethical consequences that arise from his critique. For the person living along with the author of this paper, Nietzsche’s prophetic warnings still carry great weight in any effort to understand and relate to the personal and political world. Democracy has, by and large, become the new political hegemon, and with it the attending notions of community and equality are utilized in speech with little reflection as to what their meaning. After first laying out Nietzsche’s method and mode of critique, the essay will provide an analysis of the real, ethical complications summoned to mind by Nietzsche, concerns either forgotten or rendered un-important by their immediate assumption in the “post-modern” present.
Studies in East European Thought, 2018
This article discusses the reception of Nietzsche's philosophy within the USSR. It covers the four phases of Soviet Nietzscheanism between 1920 and 1980, paying specific attention to the Soviet Nietzsche studies of the Stalin epoch. By making use of publications and archive materials, this article reconstructs the historical and logical formation of Nietzsche's negative image in post-revolutionary Russia that characterized him as an ideologist of imperialism and National Socialism. In addition to this, this article examines the facts impeding the process of Nietzsche's denazification in Russia.
Nietzsche’s irrational doctrines have contributed to the emergence of self-destructive extremism on both the right and left ends of the political spectrum. The realization of his Übermensch ideal is not about achieving greatness as an individual but rather about greatness as a collective whole, specifically as a European empire. His philosophy stands in stark contrast to genuine conservatism, which is rooted in Christian principles. Keywords: conservatism, perspectivism, traditionalism, New Right, identitarian, postmodernism, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Heraclitus, extremism, antisemitism, will to power, logos, Christianity.
Intoduction to Tracy b. Strong, ed. NIETZSCHE AND POLITICS (Ashgate, 2009),
Political Studies, 1998
Over recent years, an extraordinary number of interpretations of Nietzsche's work has appeared. I ask why he has become such an important ®gure in contemporary political debate and whether any dominant concerns can be elicited from the diverse readings of his texts. My response to both questions is that because Nietzsche has been identi®ed, by Habermas among others, as the founding father of poststructuralism, this is where debate between postmodernists and their critics is being staged. I distinguish between recent philosophical and political interpretations but argue that in both cases, what is at stake are political questions regarding authority, legitimacy and consensus. In the latter part of the article I consider attempts at reconstructing a postmodern politics out of Nietzsche's philosophy, but express some doubts about such a project.
Friedrich Nietzsche’s concept of the ubermensch was interpreted by America and Germany in two notably different ways during the early 20th century, bringing about the question of which understanding is more faithful to Nietzsche’s meaning. The advent of World War I in 1914 presented America with a depiction of Nietzsche as “the apostle of German ruthlessness and barbarism,” which offered a negative view of Nietzsche and the German people as narcissistic warmongers. This outbreak of war led to these warped interpretations of Nietzsche and his philosophy, prompting the world to see only the facade of his aphorisms, not their truer meanings, for many years. Between the world wars, Germany’s reading of Nietzsche focused on the notion that the government knows what the ubermensch is: a selfless person ready to give his life for a “greater good” of the state, which was believed to be endowed with divine mandate. The American interpretation of Nietzsche is similar but believes the philosophy of the ubermensch to be one of atheism and unadulterated power, positing man as the new god, a rugged state-defined individualism that brings out the worst in man. George Santayana argued that Nietzsche’s philosophy failed to acknowledge “immense forces beyond ourselves” which endow man with will and power. This led to the American understanding that Nietzsche wrote of a German people that believed themselves to be ubermenschen and gods among men; my research leads me to believe that this is only one possible interpretation of Nietzsche. Germany’s concept of the ubermensch was remarkably close to that of Nietzsche’s philosophy except that the true ubermensch is not a god among men underneath the omnipotent state, but rather god of his own life. World War II only worsened matters as Nietzsche’s ubermenschen were often associated with the Nazi conception of an Aryan superiority. The Nazi party viewed the ubermenschen as this Aryan race: a perfect race of men who must give their all to the state. However, there were more qualities to their ubermenschen than race, as it also incorporated a loyalty to Germany – total sacrifice of self to the state, though Nietzsche expressed his anti-nationalism in “Why I am So Wise” when he describes himself as “the last anti-political German.” The Americans then saw this Aryan Übermensch and decried Nietzsche as a proto-Nazi, despite his distaste for anti-Semites and nationalism. In this paper, I will analyze the two interpretations of Nietzsche’s philosophy through his works “The Gay Science” and “Thus Spoke Zarathustra,” Jennifer Ratner-Rosenhagen’s “American Nietzsche,” and writings from German thinkers during the wars, such as Heidegger, to support my argument that the Germans were closer to understanding Nietzsche’s ubermensch than Americans at the time.
The International Journal of the Humanities: Annual Review
Intellectual History Review, 2016
Gustav Landauer’s reading of Friedrich Nietzsche stands out as the most substantial anarchist appropriation of the German philosopher up to the present day. While his engagement has received some attention, the overall picture remains incomplete, mainly because Landauer’s numerous articles on the topic in the magazine he edited, Der Sozialist, were unavailable until recently. This paper seeks to give a full account of Landauer’s Nietzsche. I contextualise Landauer’s early reading within the emerging political reception of the German philosopher’s works and identify explicitly Nietzschean elements within his writings in order to evaluate Landauer’s ‘forerunner’ status within current post-anarchist theory. Just as contemporaries on the radical left in Wilhelmine Germany quoted Nietzsche, so did Landauer. He used the philosopher’s ideas as a code for dissidence against the powerful bureaucratic apparatus of the Social Democratic Party and to subvert their ideological dogmas. But, in contrast to many others, he did not stop there. Instead, he wrote the first Nietzsche-novel and fused various Nietzschean motifs into his anarchism, while simultaneously distancing himself from some of the problematic aspects of Nietzsche’s thought—particularly its anti-humanism, elitism, and notion of ‘hardness’.
Draft of translator's introduction to Nietzsche, Philosopher of Reaction: Towards a Political Biography, a translation of a short text by the late Italian scholar, historian of ideas and philosopher, Domenico Losurdo which will appear later this year or early 2023 with Historical Materialism. Losurdo's work originally appeared in Italian in 1997 bearing the title Nietzsche: Per una biografia politica (Roma: Manifesto Libri, Orme, 1997). Five years later, in 2002, Losurdo would publish his far longer study, Nietzsche, il ribelle aristocratico: Biografia intellettuale e bilancio critic (Turin: Bollati Boringhieri, 2002). Losurdo's great book on Nietzsche represents arguably the most significant challenge to regnant liberal, postmodernist, and feminist interpretations of the latter's work, by recourse to the methodologies of contextualising intellectual history and critical hermeneutics. Yet, despite the book's immense scholarship, weight of evidence, and intellectual significance, it would take nearly two decades for Nietzsche, il ribelle aristocratico to appear in English translation by Gregor Benton in the Historical Materialism series at Brill. Sadly, Losurdo himself would not live to see its appearance in print, passing away in June 2018. The reader of his shorter, earlier extended essay on the German philosopher of the Second Reich will however get a very clear picture of Losurdo’s larger interpretive orientation. The striking challenge his reading of Nietzsche represents to many better-known works published or translated in the Anglosphere over the last five decades is also trenchantly clear in the less than 100 pages of this work. The aim of making this work available to anglophones was to make Losurdo’s critical work, on this philosopher who continues to animate such different cohorts as academic left-liberals and far right activists, accessible to many more people, and facilitate more balanced debates surrounding everything Nietzsche thought, wrote, and has wrought. [Author's copy, do not cite]
Comparative and Continental Philosophy, 2020
Preprint version of a review essay of Hugo Drogon's Nietzsche's Great Politics and Gary Shapiro's Nietzsche and the Earth.
An Examination of the Role Played by Nietzsche's Role on Germany in the Years leading to the First World War
2023
There is a widespread feeling that modernity has come to an end, which is often accompanied by a certain anxiety. The idea that history reached its zenith with a particular thinker, say Hegel or Marx, is no longer credible. In fact, despite recent books on the “End of History,” we see that history goes on. The angst is perhaps due to the ingrained conviction that there is no absolute moment, no possibility of discovering something true and unchangeable about politics, morality or society. There is no moment in the past when the truth about man, morality and the world was revealed. We take for granted that each individual may have his or her own ethical, political and social “values”. Values, such as goodness, justice, equality, erudition, even mental health or education, are not something “given” by reality; rather, they are a historical human creation (something that may seem paradoxical, since, if man is a historical being, then the very idea that man is historical is itself historical and contingent). This historicity of history can be better understood if we compare it with past ideas about history. In ancient times, history was conceived of as a set of inquiries about what happened or as a chronicle of journeys. Even thinkers like the Sophists or Plato, who recognized the importance of change, did not expressly reflect on the “historical process”. The Stoics and Medieval thinkers, on the contrary, believed in divine providence and reflected on history and eschatology, but for them time was only “the measure of change according to before and after,” and not the essence of things. Only with Hegel does history come to be seen as the innermost core of reality, something that determines all intellectual structures and all life. However, both Hegel and those who followed him (including Marx) still perceive history as a process moving towards an ending or a perfect state – be it the attainment of absolute knowledge and the realization of the spirit in history, or the classless society. Today, however, we consider that all understanding is itself historical and related to a given cultural context. The idea of an end to history and of a “teleology” inscribed in reality appears to us as dated or outdated. We see the ideas in history as historical, and the historical process itself no longer appears to us as something we can grasp in its meaning (as if we saw it from the outside and knew where it comes from and where it is going); instead, we see it as something in the middle of which we find ourselves and whose dynamics we cannot fully understand. In fact, it would not even make sense to try to understand it, since this is not a process that occurs independently of us, but rather a process that we experience from within and for whose development we are responsible. In a sense, it is we who make history and determine it, and this making is open-ended as to its direction and purpose. This change in perspective also applies to the motivations that underlie and determine the historical process. Such motivations are no longer seen as transcendent or latent, but rather as motivations that arise from life itself and that in many cases may not be entirely rational, or may even be constitutively irrational. In fact, the entire historical process is no longer seen as rational, so that the very idea of progress has become questionable. We no longer think that we are moving toward some perfect state and that each new stage brings us closer to that. We recognize that there may have been losses, and even significant losses. They are part of the process and may even become prevalent. This becomes particularly evident if we consider the fact that modern times are often experienced or seen as a period of decadence–an idea we find already in Romanticism and which has taken different forms throughout the 20th and 21st centuries. The oft-repeated thesis that today we live in the post-truth era is only one of its latest manifestations. There is, then, no baseline from which we can understand history and obtain a secure orientation as to what we should do. As Jean-François Lyotard pointed out, it is no longer possible to think of any grand narrative or metanarrative, as was always the case up to this point. The future and future ways of understanding are therefore completely open and have to be constructed both individually and socially. Nietzsche is the first to develop this way of seeing the relationship between history and life, and takes it to its ultimate consequences. Indeed, when he criticizes philosophers for their lack of historical sense, he is not only criticizing the fact that philosophers have not realized that our way of seeing things changes over time. He is also criticizing the fact that philosophers have not understood that the historicity of ideas involves the very irrationality and incomprehensibility of the historical process.
Perspectives on Politics, 2018
2023
This paper takes it starting point from the basic assertions of Martha Nussbaum’s 1997 paper “Is Nietzsche a political thinker?". In the paper she argues that seven criteria are necessary for a serious political philosophy: 1) understanding of material need; 2) procedural justification; 3) liberty and its worth; 4) racial, ethnic and religious difference; 5) gender and family; 6) justice between nations; and 7) moral psychology. She argues, that on the first six criteria, Nietzsche has nothing to offer but does make significant contributions on the seventh. In her estimation, then, we should forget about Nietzsche as a political thinker and instead focus on the enlightenment political philosophers he found to be so boring instead. Her basic conclusion is threefold: either Nietzsche is a racialist, inegalitarian, misogynistic, and elitist, he is puerile, or he is incoherent (Nussbaum 6-9). In opposition to Nussbaum's appraisal of Nietzsche's political thought, I argue that he is in fact a serious political thinker. To present the case I focus on the inclusion of Nussbaum's six criteria in Nietzsche's Zarathustra. My focus on this work is motivated by Nussbaum's own recognition that in this work Nietzsche makes numerous allusions to Plato's Republic, a seminal work of political thought in the tradition. Surprisingly, however, Nussbaum doesn't consider Zarathustra in her appraisal of the lack of political thought in Nietzsche.
Review of Politics
Undergraduate Journal of Humanistic Studies, 2020
Friedrich Nietzsche occupies a contested, yet essential place of privilege in modern political philosophy. His poetic exhortations to readers to take personal responsibility for their beliefs and actions reveals an unsurpassed appreciation for individual liberty, but many contemporary theorists understand Nietzsche as dangerously inegalitarian, on account of his view that not all individuals are fit to achieve the highest freedom of self-creation. Nietzsche’s tolerance of, and even preference for, hierarchies of power and human worth seem to put him at odds with modern liberalism: both see individual liberty as a central goal, but liberalism also strives uncompromisingly for the general reduction of suffering and equal political participation. Nietzsche’s apparent apathy towards these latter two goals makes him a problematic ally for modern theorists, many of whom write him off as apolitical, insufficiently liberal, or even inherently facist. This essay argues that such one-dimensional interpretations of Nietzsche overlook a fundamental affinity between Nietzsche and modern liberals such as Richard Rorty and threaten to obscure essential conceptual resources that contemporary political theorists would do well to avail themselves of.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.