Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
2 pages
1 file
According to the control-based account of blame an agent A is blameworthy for X-ing iff doing X was morally wrong and A was capable of i) understanding and ii) responding to the basic demands of morality when X-ing. But consider the notion of 'taking blame.' On this view, agent B takes the punishment that A deserves so that A does not have to suffer it. In this paper I will analyze the common thought that penal substitution of blame is subject to the decisive objection that it is morally wrong to express blame towards the innocent in place of the guilty. Although there is something generally right about this objection I will argue that when certain conditions are met the concept of vicarious agency is morally plausible, indeed, in some cases it can be morally praiseworthy. Minimally, when i) the wrongdoer cannot bear the blame that he deserves, ii) it is the case that someone will have to bear the blame, iii) someone else can carry the blame that is willing, and iv) the substitute's taking the blame enables the wrongdoer to be restored and creates trust and hope in a shared sense of value and moral responsibility. I hope to show that the idea of 'restoring' the wrongdoer can motivate the plausibility of the controversial substitutionary account of blame. What will follow is a provision of an initial sketch of an area in the ethics of blame that is underexplored in the literature, yet possibly reveals an appropriate modification to the strictness of the control-based account of blame. My main purpose is to use the following discussion to encourage further debate on normative questions surrounding vicarious agency.
Philosophy Compass, Vol. 7, No. 3, 2012
Blame is usually discussed in the context of the free will problem, but recently moral philosophers have begun to examine it on its own terms. If, as many suppose, free will is to be understood as the control relevant to moral responsibility, and moral responsibility is to be understood in terms of whether blame is appropriate, then an independent inquiry into the nature and ethics of blame will be essential to solving (and, perhaps, even fully understanding) the free will problem. In this article we first survey and categorize recent accounts of the nature of blame – is it action, belief, emotion, desire, or something else? – and then we look at several proposed requirements on appropriate blame that look beyond the transgressor himself, considerations that will form part of a full account of the ethics of blame.
Some writers, such as John Fischer and Michael McKenna, have recently claimed that an agent can be morally responsible for a wrong action and yet not be blameworthy for that action. A careful examination of the claim, however, suggests two readings. On one reading, there are further conditions on blameworthiness beyond freely and wittingly doing wrong. On another innocuous reading, there are no such further conditions. Despite Fischer and McKenna's attempts to offer further conditions on blameworthiness in addition to responsibility for wrongdoing, I argue that only the innocuous reading is plausible. Once we distinguish between blame being deserved and blame being all-things-considered appropriate, we need not appeal to further conditions on blameworthiness. This discussion has important upshots regarding how compatibilists respond to certain manipulation arguments and how proponents of derived responsibility respond to criticism that agents are responsible even for outcomes that are not reasonably foreseeable.
Public Affairs Quarterly, 2020
Control accounts of moral responsibility argue that agents must possess certain capacities in order to be blameworthy for wrongdoing. This is sometimes thought to be revisionary, because reflection on our moral practices reveals that we often blame many agents who lack these capacities. This paper argues that Control accounts of moral responsibility are not too revisionary, nor too permissive, because they can still demand quite a lot from excused wrongdoers. Excused wrongdoers can acquire duties of reconciliation, which require that they improve themselves, make reparations for the harm caused, and retract the meaning expressed in the original wrong. Failure to do these things expresses a lack of regard for the victims, and can make those wrongdoers appropriate targets of blame.
Blame: Its Nature and Norms, edited by D. Justin Coates and Neal A. Tognazzini, is a vital resource for those interested in moral responsibility, especially its normative aspects. The book includes fourteen new essays-all of excellent quality-as well as a valuable and substantial introductory essay, "The Contours of Blame," by the editors.
Blame is multifarious. It can be passionate or dispassionate. It can be expressed or kept private. We blame both the living and the dead. And we blame ourselves as well as others. What’s more, we blame ourselves, not only for our moral failings, but also for our non-moral failings: for our aesthetic bad taste, gustatory self-indulgence, or poor athletic performance. And we blame ourselves both for things over which we exerted agential control (e.g., our voluntary acts) and for things over which we lacked such control (e.g., our desires, beliefs, and intentions). I argue that, despite this manifest diversity in our blaming practices, it’s possible to provide comprehensive account of blame. Indeed, I propose a set of necessary and sufficient conditions that aims to specify blame’s extension in terms of its constitution as opposed to its function. And I argue that this proposal has a number of advantages beyond accounting for blame in all its disparate forms. For one, it can account for the fact that one’s having had control over whether one was to φ is a necessary condition for one’s being fittingly blamed for having φ-ed. For another, it can account for why, unlike fitting shame, fitting blame is always deserved, which in turn explains why there is something morally problematic about ridding oneself of one’s fitting self-blame (e.g., one’s fitting guilt).
Philosophical Studies
This paper puts forward an account of blame combining two ideas that are usually set up against each other: that blame performs an important function, and that blame is justified by the moral reasons making people blameworthy rather than by its functionality. The paper argues that blame could not have developed in a purely instrumental form, and that its functionality itself demands that its functionality be effaced in favour of non-instrumental reasons for blame—its functionality is self-effacing. This notion is sharpened and it is shown how it offers an alternative to instrumentalist or consequentialist accounts of blame which preserves their animating insight while avoiding their weaknesses by recasting that insight in an explanatory role. This not only allows one to do better justice to the authority and autonomy of non-instrumental reasons for blame, but also reveals that autonomy to be a precondition of blame’s functionality. Unlike rival accounts, it also avoids the “alienati...
Instrumentalism seeks to justify praise and blame by their instrumental value. Previously considered moribund, instrumentalist approaches to responsibility and blame have recently seen a revival. This article makes two contributions to this revival. First, I defend a new, complex structure for an instrumentalist ethics of blame ('Complex Instrumentalism'). Drawing on sophisticated consequentialism and relational theories of blame, Complex Instrumentalism is dispositional in its structure and content, and pluralist and relational in its justification. Second, I argue that Complex Instrumentalism makes consequentialism more plausible. Several ethicists, including Sidgwick and Parfit, have drawn on praise and blame to defend consequentialism, for example against the charge that consequentialism is too demanding and leaves insufficient room for partiality. Those traditional arguments become far more effective, if they adopt Complex Instrumentalism. To this end, I also develop a 'multi-level' dispositional account of blameless wrongdoing. I conclude that Complex Instrumentalism is a promising compatibilist approach to blame and adds plausibility to consequentialism.
Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility, ed. Andreas Brekke, Cambridge UP, 2022
Central cases of moral blame suggest that blame presupposes that its target deserves to feel guilty, and that if one is blameworthy to some degree, one deserves to feel guilt to a corresponding degree. This, some think, is what explains why being blameworthy for something presupposes having had a strong kind of control over it: only given such control is the suffering involved in feeling guilt deserved. This chapter argues that all this is wrong. As evidenced by a wider range of cases, blame doesn’t presuppose that the target deserves to feel guilt and doesn’t necessarily aim at the target’s suffering in recognition of what they have done. On the constructive side, the chapter offers an explanation of why, in many cases of moral blameworthiness, the agent nevertheless does deserve to feel guilt. The explanation leans on a general account of moral and non-moral blame and blameworthiness and a version of the popular idea that moral blame targets agents’ objectionable quality of will. Given the latter idea, the morally blameworthy have harmed the standing of some person or value, giving rise to obligations to give correspondingly less relative weight to their own standing, and so, sometimes, to their own suffering.
Philosophical Psychology, 2021
Why do we find agents less blameworthy when they face mitigating circumstances, and what does this show about philosophical theories of moral responsibility? We present novel evidence that the tendency to mitigate the blameworthiness of agents is driven both by the perception that they are less normatively competent—in particular, less able to know that what they are doing is wrong—and by the perception that their behavior is less attributable to their deep selves. Consequently, we argue that philosophers cannot rely on the case strategy to support the Normative Competence theory of moral responsibility over the Deep Self theory. However, we also outline ways in which further empirical and philosophical work would shift the debate, by showing that there is a significant departure between ordinary concepts and corresponding philosophical concepts, or by focusing on a different type of coherence with ordinary judgments.
Philosophical Studies, 2021
This paper puts forward an account of blame combining two ideas that are usually set up against each other: that blame performs an important function, and that blame is justified by the moral reasons making people blameworthy rather than by its functionality. The paper argues that blame could not have developed in a purely instrumental form, and that its functionality itself demands that its functionality be effaced in favour of non-instrumental reasons for blame – its functionality is self-effacing. This notion is sharpened and it is shown how it offers an alternative to instrumentalist or consequentialist accounts of blame which preserves their animating insight while avoiding their weaknesses by recasting that insight in an explanatory role. This not only allows one to do better justice to the authority and autonomy of non-instrumental reasons for blame, but also reveals that autonomy to be a precondition of blame's functionality. Unlike rival accounts, it also avoids the "alienation effect" that renders blame unstable under reflection by undercutting the authority of the moral reasons which enable it to perform its function in the first place. It instead yields a vindicatory explanation that strengthens our confidence in those moral reasons.
Bernáth, László, Blame and Fault: Toward a Conative Theory of Blame. Disputatio: International Journal of Philosophy, 12 (59). pp. 371-94. , 2020
New Essays, 2015
International Journal of Theology, Philosophy and Science, 2018
Social Theory and Practice, 2024
doctoral dissertation, 2013
Journal of Law and Politics, 2007
Philosophia, Vol. 41, No. 4, 2013
Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 2021
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 82, No. 2, 2011
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 2010