Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
1974, Philosophy and Rhetoric
AI
Lloyd Bitzer argues that the rhetorical situation is a controlling force in rhetorical activity, emphasizing the objective elements such as exigence, audience, and constraints. In contrast, Richard Vatz posits that the rhetor has creative agency in shaping the rhetorical situation, challenging Bitzer's deterministic view. The paper proposes a reconciliatory approach that conceptualizes rhetoric as an art of topics, enabling the rhetor to navigate indeterminate contexts through both integrity and receptivity, ultimately re-framing the relationship between the rhetor and the situation.
Philosophy & Rhetoric, 1973
In the opening Unes of "The Rhetorical Situation," Lloyd Bitzer states, "if someone says, That is a dangerous situation, his words suggest the présence of events, persons or objects which threaten him, someone else or something of value. If someone remarks, I find myself in an embarrassing situation, again the statement implies certain situational characteristics."1 These Statements do not imply "situational characteristics" at all. The Statements may ostensibly describe situations, but they actually only inform us as to the phenomenological perspective of the speaker. There can be little argument that the speakers believe they f eel f ear or embarrassment. Their Statements do not, however, tell us about qualities within the situation. Kenneth Burke once wrote of literary critics who attributed to others the characteristic of seeking escape: "While apparenüy defining a trait of the person referred to, thè term hardly did more than convey the attitude of the person making the référence."2 The same goes for the attribution of traits to a situation. It is a fitting of a scene into a category or catégories found in the head of the observer. No situation can hâve a nature independent of the perception of its interpréter or independent of the rhetoric with which he chooses to characterize it. In his article Bitzer states, "Rhetorical discourse is called into existence by situation"3 and "It seems clear that rhetoric is situational."4 This perspective on rhetoric and "situation" requires a "realist" philosophy of meaning. This philosophy has important and, I believe, unfortunate implications for rhetoric. In this article I plan to discuss Bitzer's view and its implications and suggest a différent perspective with a différent philosophy of meaning from which to view the relationship between "situations" and rhetoric.
This study offers a critical analysis of Lloyd F. Bitzer's model of rhetorical criticism, "the rhetorical situation." Since the article of the same name in 1968, this model has come under intense scrutiny and criticism, yet remains today a substantive approach to rhetorical criticism. This study evaluates the critiques of Richard Vatz and Barbara Biesecker and concludes with an analysis of Bitzer's model in light of those critiques.
2013
There is no doubt that the tinderbox of the American Revolution existed long before Thomas Paine immigrated to the American colonies in 1774. However, few could argue that Paine's pamphlet Common Sense was not one of the sparks that contributed to America's political and military revolution that led to the Declaration of Independence in 1776. According to Merrill Jensen, author of The Founding of a Nation: A History of the American Revolution, 1763-1776, the ideas that Paine expressed in his pamphlet, Common Sense, were not his own. Jensen claims that Paine was merely using his rhetorical skills to translate the complex ideas of Paine's contemporaries into a more common language as a means of communicating with the average readers of Paine's day. 1 Using the tool that Lloyd Bitzer gave students of rhetoric in his 1968 article, "The Rhetorical Situation," this paper will examine the social, cultural, and historical context of Thomas Paine's Common Sense. According to Lloyd Bitzer, discourse comes into existence as a response to a given situation. Just as an answer follows a question or a solution follows a problem, discourse follows a given rhetorical situation. Essentially, the rhetorical situation must exist as a necessary condition that precedes discourse and discourse is rhetorical discourse according to how it functions as a response to the rhetorical situation that made the utterance possible. In addition, the utterance itself is limited by the rhetorical situation. The situation controls the response in much the same way that a question controls the answer to the question. For Bitzer, the rhetorical situation can be defined as: A complex of persons, events, objects, and relations presenting an actual or potential exigence which can be completely or partially removed if discourse, introduced into the situation, can so constrain human decision or action as to bring about the significant modification of the exigence.2 Bitzer goes on to add that "prior to the creation and presentation of the discourse, there are three constituents of any rhetorical situation." Bitzer calls these three constituents
[Currently in preparation for publication.] This thesis examines rhetorical situation theory. Drawing upon previous literature ranging from the original Bitzer-Vatz-(Consigny) debate through recent genre studies on rhetorical situation, I present a modified version of rhetorical situation theory in light of the common ideas, disputes, strengths, and limitations of earlier works. I begin with a review of important literature in Chapter Two in order to illustrate both the similarities and differences in other theories. Then, in Chapter Three, I discuss the importance of audience, particularly fictional audiences, to the rhetorical situation. I present a modified version of rhetorical situation theory in Chapter Four and illustrate the rhetorical situation by discussing examples in Chapter Five. I also offer a universal example for rhetorical situations, one that is not designed to support any theory in particular.
Argumentation, 2000
'Rhetorical Analysis Within a Pragma-Dialectical Framework' raises three questions. First, what is the relation between the methods of winning a dispute and the methods of securing agreement studied in pragma-dialectics? What is the relation between rhetoric and dialectic? This is a question to which van Eemeren and Houtlosser offer a clear answer, but I will invite them to reconsider in light of my other two questions. Second, how do the methods of verbal manipulation in general, whether competitive or cooperative, relate to the methods used to arrive at something greater than agreement, such as truth or the accurate representation of nature? This second question could be posed as the relation between dialectic and rhetoric and the methods of science. Third, discourse often has purposes that have nothing to do with resolving disputes, and which therefore do not reach the threshold at which dialectic, for van Eemeren and Houtlosser, begins. Often people speak merely to be heard, to express themselves and create their identities within a community. Just as I wonder about the relation between both rhetoric and dialectic and science, I wonder about their relation to purely expressive discourse, a connection perhaps hinted at in Aristotle's discussion of epideictic rhetoric, but surely needing more analysis.
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
In B. Hampe, ed., From Perception to Meaning: Image Schemas in Cognitive Linguistics, 443-473. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 2005
This is an essay in Applied Cognitive Rhetoric. It seeks to establish a renewed connection between Cognitive Semantics and rhetorical theory at the level of pa-tient textual analysis. Sustained cognitive rhetorical analysis of canonical rhetorical texts has been a rare occurrence in Cognitive Linguistics forums, despite Turner’s (1991) seminal work in this area. In this essay, I apply Talmy’s (2000) system of Force Dynamics and Event Frames to two paragon rhetorical texts: the Preamble to President George W. Bush’s National Security Report and Abraham Lincoln’s Second Innaugural Address, the first an example of the deliberative genre, the second an example of the epideictic genre. After a brief discussion of the rhetorical situations to which these two texts were responding, I give a systematic overview of Talmy’s force dynamic and event frame systems. The remainder of the essay comprises a patient analysis of the schematic force dynamic patterns and support-ing event frames inherent in each text. The intent of each analysis is to reveal how these schematic patterns shape the logic and emotion of each argument.
Course Description: This course is a theoretical-historical review of writings about rhetoric in the Western tradition up through the Enlightenment. It is based upon the assumption that there is no single, stable entity in that tradition called " rhetoric. " Instead, different writers organize that term in relationship to terms referencing other discourses and practices. Each way of situating rhetoric in a world of texts and action is also a way of understanding human experience in general. This course will cover various important figures in the history of rhetoric. We start our investigation with the thinkers from ancient Greece-Plato, Protagoras, Gorgias, Isocrates, and Aristotle. We will examine what they believe rhetoric is, what its value is, and what role it should play in ethics and politics. Important thinkers from the Roman world will also be examined. We'll talk about how Cicero, Quintilian, and various stoics conceptualized and practiced rhetoric. Augustine, Christine de Pizan, and Immanuel Kant will also be examined with at the conclusion of the class. We will emphasize primary sources for all of these figures, although I will expose you to selected secondary sources when it seems beneficial.
Argument & Computation, 2017
Note: Rhetoric has an extensive technical vocabulary. In this introduction, we explain these terms as we go along. The authors of the papers in this special issue do the same. But it can be easy to get lost in a forest of so many novel terms. So we provide a glossary at the end of this introduction.
The topic of rhetoric and stylistics in philosophy opens up the broader question for the Western tradition of the relationship between rhetoric and philosophy. Rhetoric can be considered in two ways: either as a separate form of discourse, used by certain individuals at certain times for certain distinct purposes (persuasion), or as a general feature of all discourse insofar as every linguistic act unfolds in a style and aims to produce an effect on the receiver (move, instruct, entertain, deceive, convince. Philosophy likewise has gone through periods of institutional and societal isolation from other forms of discourse as well as periods where it reigned as queen over all other sciences and modes of expression. In short, both can have either particular applications or universal significance. This article will pursue the different modes of interaction between rhetoric and philosophy, first historically and then in terms of systematic and conceptual issues.
Let us start with some reflection over this excerpt from the speech of a high-profile political leader:
The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Semantics
In accord with the tradition of using idiosyncratic terminology, I will call them "coherence relations". On the Coherence and Structure of Discourse, Jerry R. Hobbs (1985) 1 What is a rhetorical relation? Let us start with an illustration. Below is a joke from the show Right Wing Comedian performed by the Britisch stand-up comedian Leo Kearse at the Edinburgh Fringe Festival 2018. 1 Obviously, this is not an arbitrary sequence of utterances. The listener or reader immediately recognises that the utterances hold together forming one meaningful whole. The way the utterances are related can be characterised in rational terms. In (1-a), Kearse's character states that he has sympathy for Donald Trump, and the subsequent clauses (1-b)-(1-f) provide an explanation of why he feels that way. Different parts of that explanation are also interrelated. (1-b) and (1-c) do no more than telling a story of Trump's presidential campaign, that is, they represent events taking place in a sequence. (1-d) represents an unexpected twist in the story: Trump winning the election against his own attempts not to (1-c), as also signaled by the contrastive conjunction but. (1-e) then presents a consequence, or result of Trump's victory (1-d). Finally, (1-f) draws a parallel between Trump's presidential campaign experience in the sequence (1-b)-(1-e) and the speaker's own experience of applying for jobs. (1) a. I've got some sympathy for Trump. b. He went for a job, c. tried to throw the interview d. but accidentally got it e. and now he hates it. f. Reminds me of every interview I had for jobs I didn't want when I was on benefits. We say that the different parts of the discourse in (1) are connected by means of rhetorical relations (henceforth RRs) such as Explanation, Narration, Contrast, Result and Parallel. The rhetorical structure of the discourse is represented schematically in Figure 1. More generally, the identification of RRs is a way (one way) to characterise the coherence of text and discourse. In the past three decades, research on RRs has come up with a variety of frameworks which differ in terms of both definition and inventory of RRs (cf. e.g. Hovy
Philosophy & rhetoric, 1989
This is a book with a practical purpose. It aims to give students a handy reference to the background knowledge of rhetorical terms demanded of them by critical and theoretical texts in the humanities. A common vocabulary is used today for cultural criticism and theory and for related sub-disciplinary and inter-disciplinary discourses (in philosophy, literary criticism, and indeed all the humanities). The western world's twenty first century 'renaissance' scholar needs to be fluent in the vocabulary which carries her across these disciplines. An important part of this vocabulary is in the rhetorical terms we read and write, reason and refute by. These are the means by which we tell and receive the stories that explain the world. They are the means by which we imagine our own and others' ideas. To read and equally to write theory today one needs to be able to negotiate a way among these tropic motions; one needs to master the terms with which motions in meaning are described. Amorphous and difficult as this kind of learning is, it is of vital and personal importance. Through it one learns how one means what one means. It is through that kind of understanding one gets to decide what to mean.
Theory and Society, 1987
The key question in rhetorical analysis concerns the relationships that the speakers (or writers of texts) construct between themselves and the audience with their texts. Who is the speaker in the text? Who does the text address? How does the "matter itself", the topic of the text, function as part of the addressing? How does the text carry the opportunities for social relationships, links and distinctions, harmony and discord? Ultimately, we are dealing with the political aspects of a text: how does it invite you to act?
" Contentious " is a doubly valenced word: it connotes both " strifing " and " striving. " Those practicing rhetorical arts have historically been seen as contentious in the first sense: sowing strife through agonism, play, and dissoi logoi—especially around the terms that we see as central to our activity. Rhetorical theorists draw on this heritage to make contentions in the second sense, striving to sharpen our conceptual vocabulary for apprehending communication in all the weirdly diverse ways that it manifests. This graduate course focuses on contentious terms in rhetorical theory past and present: terms that animate fiery scholarly conversations, stimulate competition among different schools of thought, demand clarification and complication of founding assumptions, stretch the boundaries of rhetorical knowledge in new directions, and spark new theoretical insights that help us see the world differently. Rhetoric's history is populated with terms that are essentially contested and essentially contestable; the task of the course is to help students enter this broader contest of rhetorical theory with their own unique contributions.
Informal Logic, 1993
Prudence has long been an important topic for rhetorical theorists and its place in intellectual history is becoming increasingly well documented. This essay develops a conception of prudence as an ideological construct, a term crafted in the history of its public usages to govern the relationship between common sense and political action as enacted in the name of historically situated social actors. From this perspective, prudence represents the recursive interaction between a rhetoric of judgment and the grounds on which that rhetoric is evaluated by a historically particular community of arguers. A case study of the 1991 U.S. Senate debate regarding the authorization of offensive military action in the Persian Gulf illustrates how competing standards of prudential judgment are crafted and evaluated in discursive controversy.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.