Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2013, Proceedings of Socreal 2013 3rd International Workshop on Philosophy and Ethics of Social Reality 2013
AI
This paper explores new logical frameworks for understanding ceteris paribus preferences in the context of modal logic. It delves into semantics related to preference, defines key concepts such as priority graphs, and presents a novel axiomatization approach. By analyzing the dynamics and implications of preferences under ceteris paribus conditions, the research contributes to a more nuanced understanding of decision-making processes in varying contexts, particularly in economics.
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2009
This paper presents a new modal logic for ceteris paribus preferences understood in the sense of “all other things being equal”. This reading goes back to the seminal work of Von Wright in the early 1960’s and has returned in computer science in the 1990’s and in more abstract “dependency logics” today. We show how it differs from ceteris paribus as “all other things being normal”, which is used in contexts with preference defeaters. We provide a semantic analysis and several completeness theorems. We show how our system links up with Von Wright’s work, and how it applies to game-theoretic solution concepts, to agenda setting in investigation, and to preference change. We finally consider its relation with infinitary modal logics.
Erkenntnis, 1989
A possible world semantics for preference is developed. The remainder operator (_1.) is used to give precision to the notion that two states of the world are as similar as possible, given a specified difference between them. A general structure is introduced for preference relations between states of affairs, and three types of such preference relations are defined. It is argued that one of them, "actual preference", corresponds closely to the concept of preference in informal discourse. Its logical properties are studied and shown to be plausible.
2009
In the last few years, preference logic and in particular, the dynamic logic of preference change, has suddenly become a live topic in my Amsterdam and Stanford environments. At the request of the editors, this article explains how this interest came about, and what is happening. I mainly present a story around some recent dissertations and supporting papers, which are found in the references. There is no pretense at complete coverage of preference logic (for that, see Hanson 2001) or even of preference change (Hanson 1995). Agency, information, and preference Human agents acquire and transform information in different ways: they observe, or infer by themselves, and often also, they ask someone else. Traditional philosophical logics describe part of this behaviour, the 'static' properties produced by such actions: in particular, agents' knowledge and belief at some given moment. But rational human activity is goal-driven, and hence we also need to describe agents' evaluation of different states of the world, or of outcomes of their actions. Here is where preference logic have come to describe what agents prefer, while current dynamic logics describe effects of their physical actions. In the limit, all these things have to come together in understanding even such a simple scenario as a game, where we need to look at what players want, what they can observe and guess, and which moves and long-term strategies are available to them in order to achieve their goals. There are two dual aspects to this situation. The static description of what agents know, believe, or prefer at any given moment has long been performed by standard systems of philosophical logic since the 1950s -of course, with continued debate surrounding the merits of particular proposals. But there is also the dynamics of actions and events that produce information and generate attitudes Overview This paper is mainly based on some recent publications in the Amsterdam environment over the last three years. Indeed, 'dynamics' presupposes an account of 'statics', and hence we first give a brief survey of preference logic in a simple modal format using binary comparison relations between possible worlds -on the principle that 'small is beautiful'. We also describe a recent alternative approach, where world preferences are generated from criteria or constraints. We show how to dynamify both views by adding explicit events that trigger preference change in the models, and we sketch how the resulting systems connect. Next, we discuss some entanglements between preference, knowledge and belief, and what this means for combined dynamic logics. On top of this, we also show how more delicate aspects of preference should be incorporated, such as its striking 'ceteris paribus' character, which was already central in Von Wright 1963. Finally, we relate our considerations to social choice theory and game theory. Preference is a very multi-faceted notion: we can prefer one individual object, or one situation, over another -but preference can also be directed toward kinds of objects or generic types of situation, often defined by propositions. Both perspectives make sense, and a bona fide 'preference logic' should do justice to all of them eventually. We start with a simple scenario on the object/world side, leaving other options for later. In this paper, we start with a very simple setting. Modal models M = (W, ≤, V) consist of a set of worlds W (but they really stand for any sort of objects that are subject to evaluation and comparison), a 'betterness' relation ≤ between worlds ('at least as good as'), and a valuation V for proposition letters at worlds (or, for unary properties of objects). In principle, the comparison relation may be different for different agents, but in what follows, we will suppress agent subscripts ≤ i whenever possible for greater readability. Also, we use the artificial term 'betterness' to stress that this is an abstract comparison relation, making no claim yet concerning the natural rendering of the intuitive term 'preference', about which some people hold passionate proprietary opinions. Still, this semantics is entirely natural and concrete. Just think of decision theory, where worlds (standing for outcomes of actions) are compared as to utility, or Here move is the union of all one-step move relations available to players, and * denotes the reflexive-transitive closure of a relation. The formula then says there is no alternative move to the BI-prescription at the current node all of whose outcomes would be better than the BI-solution. Thus, modal preference logic seems to go well with games. 3 But there are more examples. Already Boutilier 1994 observed how such a simple modal language can also define conditional assertions, normally studied per se as a complex new binary modality (Lewis 1973), and how one can then analyze their logic in standard terms. 4 For instance, in modal models with finite pre-orders (see below), the standard truth definition of a conditional A ⇒ B reads as 'B is true in all maximal A-worlds' -and this clause can be written as the following modal combination: with [] some appropriate universal modality. While this formula may look complex at first, the point is that the inferential behaviour of the conditional, including its well-known non-monotonic features, can now be completely understood via the base logic for the unary modalities, say, as a sub-theory of modal S4. Moreover, the modal language easily defines variant notions whose introduction seems a big deal in conditional logic, such as existential versions saying that each A-world sees at least one maximal A-world which is B. Of course, explicit separate axiomatizations of these defined notions retain an independent interest: but we now see the whole picture. 5 Constraints on betterness orders Which properties should a betterness relation have? Many authors like to work with total orders, satisfying reflexivity, transitivity, and connectedness. This is also common practice in decision theory and game theory, since 3 This, and also the following examples are somewhat remarkable, because there has been a widespread prejudice that modal logic is not very suitable to formalizing preference reasoning. 4 This innovative move is yet to become common knowledge in the logical literature. 5 There still remains the question of axiomatizing such defined notions per se: and that may be seen as the point of the usual completeness theorems in conditional logic. Also, Halpern 1997 axiomatized a defined notion of preference of this existential sort.
1994
Decision-theoretic preferences specify the relative desirability of all possible outcomes of alternative plans. In order to express general patterns of preference holding in a domain, we require a language that can refer directly to preferences over classes of outcomes as well as individuals. We present the basic concepts of a theory of meaning for such generic comparatives to facilitate their incremental capture and exploitation in automated reasoning systems. Our semantics lifts comparisons of individuals to comparisons of classes "other things being equal" by means of contextual equivalences, equivalence relations among individuals that vary with the context of application. We discuss implications of the theory for representing preference information.
Ceteris Paribus clauses in reasoning are used to allow for defeaters of norms, rules or laws, such as in von Wright’s example “I prefer my raincoat over my umbrella, everything else being equal”. In earlier work, a logical analysis is offered in which sets of formulas Γ, embedded in modal operators, provide necessary and sufficient conditions for things to be equal in ceteris paribus clauses. For most laws, the set of things allowed to vary is small, often finite, and so Γ is typically infinite. Yet the axiomatisation they provide is restricted to the special and atypical case in which Γ is finite. We address this problem by being more flexible about ceteris paribus conditions, in two ways. The first is to offer an alternative, slightly more general semantics, in which the set of formulas only give necessary but not (necessarily) sufficient conditions. This permits a simple axiomatisation.
Outstanding Contributions to Logic, 2014
It has usually been assumed that monadic value notions can be defined in terms of dyadic value notions, whereas definitions in the opposite direction are not possible. In this paper, inspired by van Benthem's work, it is shown that the latter direction is feasible with a method in which shifts in context have a crucial role. But although dyadic preference orderings can be defined from context-indexed monadic notions, the monadic notions cannot be regained from the preference relation that they gave rise to. Two formal languages are proposed in which reasoning about context can be represented in a fairly general way. One of these is a modal language much inspired by van Benthem's work. Throughout the paper the focus is on relationships among the value notions "good", "bad", and "better". Other interpretations like "tall" and "taller" are equally natural. It is hoped that the results of this paper can be relevant for the analysis of natural language comparatives and of vague predicates in general.
2006
Preference is a basic notion in human behaviour, underlying such varied phenomena as individual rationality in the philosophy of action and game theory, obligations in deontic logic (we should aim for the best of all possible worlds), or collective decisions in social choice theory. Also, in a more abstract sense, preference orderings are used in conditional logic or non-monotonic reasoning as a way of arranging worlds into more or less plausible ones. The field of preference logic (cf. Hansson ) studies formal systems that can express and analyze notions of preference between various sorts of entities: worlds, actions, or propositions. The art is of course to design a language that combines perspicuity and low complexity with reasonable expressive power. In this paper, we take a particularly simple approach. As preferences are binary relations between worlds, they naturally support standard unary modalities. In particular, our key modality ♦ϕ will just say that is ϕ true in some world which is at least as good as the current one. Of course, this notion can also be indexed to separate agents. The essence of this language is already in [4], but our semantics is more general, and so are our applications and later language extensions. Our modal language can express a variety of preference notions between propositions. Moreover, as already suggested in [9], it can "deconstruct" standard conditionals, providing an embedding of conditional logic into more standard modal logics. Next, we take the language to the analysis of games, where some sort of preference logic is evidently needed ([23] has a binary modal analysis different from ours). We show how a qualitative unary preference modality suffices for defining Nash Equilibrium in strategic games, and also the Backward Induction solution for finite extensive games. Finally, from a technical perspective, our treatment adds a new twist. Each application considered in this paper suggests the need for some additional access to worlds before the preference modality can unfold its true power. For this purpose, we use various extras from the modern literature: the global modality, further hybrid logic operators, action modalities from propositional dynamic logic, and modalities of individual and distributed knowledge from epistemic logic. The total package is still modal, but we can now capture a large variety of new notions. Finally, our emphasis in this paper is wholly on expressive power. Axiomatic completeness results for our languages can be found in the follow-up paper [27].
In practical decision-making, it seems clear that if we hope to make an optimal or at least defensible decision, we must weigh our alternatives against each other and come to a principled judgment between them. In the formal literature of classical decision theory, it is taken as an indispensable axiom that cardinal rankings of alternatives be defined for all possible alternatives over which we might have to decide. Whether there are any items " beyond compare " is thus a crucial question for decision theorists to consider when constructing a formal framework. At the very least, it seems problematic to presuppose that no such incommensurability is possible on the grounds that it would make formalizing axioms for decision-making more difficult, or even intractable. With this in mind, I plan to argue in this paper that a formal notion of comparability can be introduced to the classical understanding of preference relations such that the question of comparability between alternatives can be taken non-trivially. Building on the work of Richard Bradley and Ruth Chang, I argue that the comparability relation should be understood to be transitive but not complete. I contend that this understanding of comparability within decision theory can explain both why we believe that some alternatives may be incommensurable, yet we are still able to make justified decisions despite incomplete preference relations. In Section I, I lay the groundwork for understanding the conceptual relationship between comparability and commensurability with respect to decision-making. In Section II, I will argue that Bradley's definition of the preference relation with comparability leads to absurdity and contradiction due to a small oversight, which I propose to remedy. Then,
Reasoning about preferences is a major issue in many decision making problems. Recently, a new logic for handling preferences, called qualitative choice logic (QCL), was presented. This logic adds to classical propositional logic a new connective, called ordered disjunction symbolized by ×. That new connective is used to express preferences between alternatives. Intuitively, if A and B are propositional formulas then A ×B means: "if possible A, but if A is impossible then at least B". One of the important limitations of QCL is that it does not correctly deal with negated and conditional preferences. Conditional rules that involve preferences are expressed using propositional implication. However, using QCL semantics, there is no difference between such material implication "(KLM ×Air France) ⇒ Hotel Package" and the purely propositional formula "(Air France∨KLM) ⇒ Hotel Package". Moreover, the negation in QCL misses some desirable properties from propositional calculus. This paper first proposes an extension of QCL language to universally quantified first-order logic framework. Then, we propose two new logics that correctly address QCL's limitations. Both of them are based on the same QCL language, but define new non-monotonic consequence relations. The first logic, called PQCL (prioritized qualitative choice logic), is particularly adapted for handling prioritized preferences, while the second one, called QCL+ (positive qualitative choice logic), is appropriate for handling positive preferences. In both cases, we show that any set of preferences, can equivalently be transformed into a set of basic preferences from which efficient inferences can be applied. Lastly, we show how our logics can be applied to alert correlation.
1997
... Relationships between As-sumptions. Doctoral thesis, University of Kaiser-slautern, Kaiserslautern, 1992. [Junker, 1995] U. Junker. Buroeinrichtung mit EX-CEPT II. In F. di Primio, editor, Methoden der Kunsthchen Intelligenz fur Graphikanwendungen. Addison-Wesley, 1995. ...
2020
Well-behaved preferences (e.g., total pre-orders) are a cornerstone of several areas in artificial intelligence, from knowledge representation, where preferences typically encode likelihood comparisons, to both game and decision theories, where preferences typically encode utility comparisons. Yet weaker (e.g., cyclical) structures of comparison have proven important in a number of areas, from argumentation theory to tournaments and social choice theory. In this paper we provide logical foundations for reasoning about this type of preference structures where no obvious best elements may exist. Concretely, we compare and axiomatize a number of ways in which the concepts of maximality and optimality can be lifted to this general class of preferences. In doing so we expand the scope of the long-standing tradition of the logical analysis of preference.
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2014
In [1] the authors developed a logical system based on the definition of a new non-classical connective ⊗ capturing the notion of reparative obligation. The system proved to be appropriate for handling well-known contrary-to-duty paradoxes but no model-theoretic semantics was presented. In this paper we fill the gap and define a suitable possible-world semantics for the system for which we can prove soundness and completeness. The semantics is a preference-based non-normal one extending and generalizing semantics for classical modal logics.
Synthese, 2010
Preference is a key area where analytic philosophy meets philosophical logic. I start with two related issues: reasons for preference, and changes in preference, first mentioned in von Wright's book The Logic of Preference but not thoroughly explored there. I show how these two issues can be handled together in one dynamic logical framework, working with structured two-level models, and we investigate the resulting dynamics of reason-based preference in some detail. Next, we study the foundational issue of entanglement between preference and beliefs, and relate the resulting richer logics to belief revision theory and decision theory.
Preference Change, 2009
In this paper we consider preference over objects. We show how this preference can be derived from priorities, properties of these objects, a concept which is initially from optimality theory. We do this both in the case when an agent has complete information and in the case when an agent only has beliefs about the properties. After the single agent case we also consider the multi-agent case. In each of these cases, we construct preference logics, some of them extending the standard logic of belief. This leads to interesting connections between preference and beliefs. We strengthen the usual completeness results for logics of this kind to representation theorems. The representation theorems describe the reasoning that is valid for preference relations that have been obtained from priorities. In the multi-agent case, these representation theorems are strengthened to the special cases of cooperative and competitive agents. We study preference change with regard to changes of the priority sequence, and change of beliefs. We apply the dynamic epistemic logic approach, and in consequence reduction axioms are presented. We conclude with some possible directions for future work.
Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 1994
The notion ofpreference is central to most forms of nonmonotonic reasoning. Shoham, in his dissertation, used this notion to give a single semantical point of view from which most nonmonotonic reasoning systems could be studied. In this paper, we study the notion of preference closely and devise a class of logics of preference that extract the logicalcore of the notion of preference. Earlier attempts have been largely unsuccessful, because of adoption as matters of logic of certain theory-specific preference principles such asasymmetry andtransitivity. Soundness, completeness and decidability proofs for the logics are given. We define the notion of a preferential theory and reframe nonmonotonicity as a symbolic optimization problem where defaults are coded aspreference criteria which place preference orders on the models of a first-order theory. We study the relationship between normal default theories and show the correspondence between models of extensions and optimal worlds. We give a preferential account of some forms of circumscription. Thelocal nature of preference logic is contrasted with the global notion of normality and preference that is used by conditional logics of normality and cumulative inference operations. In related papers, we give a completely declarative semantics for the stable models of normal logic programs, a deontic logic based on preferences that is free of the anomalies of standard deontic logic, and extend Horn clause logic programming to impose partial orders on the bodies of clauses as declarative specification of the relaxation criteria for the truth-hood of the heads.
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2015
In [13] the authors developed a logical system based on the definition of a new non-classical connective ⊗ originally capturing the notion of reparative obligation. The operator ⊗ and the system were proved to be appropriate for rather handling well-known contrary-to-duty paradoxes. Later on, a suitable modeltheoretic possible-world semantics has been developed [4, 5]. In this paper we show how a version of this semantics can be used to develop a sound and complete logic of preference and offer a suitable possible-world semantics. The semantics is a sequence-based non-normal one extending and generalising semantics for classical modal logics.
Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 1993
This paper is an attempt to clear the following charge leveled against preference logics: preference logics rest upon the mistaken belief that concept construction can satisfactorily be carded out in isolation from theory construction (J. Mullen, Metaphilosophy 10(1979)247-255). We construct a logic of preference that is fundamental in the sense that it does not commit itself to any allegedly obvious or intuitive-and in actuality, theory specificpreference principles. A unique feature of our construction is that preference orderings are placed upon possible worlds. While this has been done before in the work of S.O. Hansson and N. Rescher, among others, we do not derive a binary preference relation-from these orders-that acts on individual propositions. Instead, we provide the syntactic means to impose the preference orderings among worlds. Thus, unlike Hansson, we do not need to assume a priori that our preference orderings be transitive. Such properties can be axiomatized. The close connections between preferences and obligations, in particular their normative nature, then allow us to derive a deontic logic that is free of the paradoxes of standard deontic logic. It is interesting to note here that this work arose in an attempt to provide a logical characterization of document description and layout. Layout directives can be succinctly represented as preference criteria. 9 ~t DmFiff3vE~162 FAw~v. Thus, we have a spectrum of indifferences, ranging from admissibles on the one (weaker) end to dismissibles on the other end. (These operators will be very useful in our treatment of deontic logic.) The logic @2 is equivalent to a bimodal logic that characterizes complementary bimodal frames. To make the connection explicit, let us consider a modal logic ffC[ with two primitive operators f-l~ and I-'12 and the semantics cast in terms of frames (~ ~1, ~2), where ~2 is the complement of ~1. Given the usual interpretation of I"ql and 1-'12, we have the following translation a of @ formulae into formulae of ~[. This translation preserves validity.
IEEE Transactions on Fuzzy Systems, 2019
It is widely accepted that distributivity properties play a key role in fuzzy research, especially in fuzzy control. Making use of the solution of the autodistributivity functional equations, we give a characterisation of all the four types of distributivity of fuzzy implication. The necessary and sufficient condition for all the four distributive equation is that the operator belongs to the pliant operator class. This theorem leads to a new implication called preference implication. It is well known that there is no implication in (continuous-valued) fuzzy logic that satisfies all the properties that are valid in (classical) twovalued logic. We show that preference implication fulfills: (i) the law of contraposition, (ii) the T-conditionality, (iii) the ordering property, (iv) the exchange principle, (v) the law of importation, (vi) the identity principle and (vii) the general hypothetical reasoning. Preference implication has a ν parameter i.e., the fixed point of the negation. This ν value serves as a threshold and with this value we can go back by projection to the two-valued logic case. At the end of the article we indicate that the preference implication is closely related to the preference relation used in multicriteria decision making. We point that if the preference implication is multiplicative transitive and reciprocal, then the pliant system is reduced to some particular generator function of Dombi.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.