Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
• The question of transformation When we try to think rationally about the status of the child, the first difficulty we meet is due to the gulf which separates the infant he starts out as and the adult he will become: how can we understand what he is without assigning two distinct natures to beings so different from one another? And how, then, can we think out an unbroken link (and not a qualitative leap) between these two states of human nature? These questions are extremely problematic in Spinoza's philosophy, which understands changes by degrees (and not by natures) and which refuses to envisage the succession in time of two different natures in one and the same individual. Now, Spinoza doesn't avoid this problem; on the contrary, he explicitly picks it out in the scholium of proposition 39 of the fourth part of Ethics, when he writes about babies that "a man of advanced years believes their nature to be so different of his own that he could not be persuaded that he had ever been a baby if he did not draw a parallel from other cases". In other words, neither our memory nor our reason are able to convince us that we've ever been in that state (which, because of the great difference between it and our actual "state", does rather appear to us as a different "nature"); the observation of others and "knowledge from casual experience" which can be drawn from it are only able to make us believe it.
childhood and philosophy, 2021
Baruch Spinoza, the 17th century philosopher best known for his metaphysical rigor and the radical heterodoxy of his conception of God as Nature, did not say much about children or childhood. Nevertheless, his few mentions of children in his masterpiece, the Ethics, raise fascinating questions of autarky, rationality and mind-body relations as they are perceived in the contrast between children and adults. Generally, philosophical theories of childhood benefit greatly from a strong metaphysical foundation. Spinoza's philosophy, which has recently been gaining considerable attention by contemporary neuroscientists and psychologists, can serve as stable and fertile ground for developing a strong philosophy of childhood. In this paper I address the Spinozistic conception of a flourishing, happy human and the way this understanding of human excellence reflects on his understanding of children and childhood. I argue that the use of Spinozistic concepts can be valuable in the analysis of children and childhood-especially essence, striving to persevere in being, and the nature of the imagination. Spinoza's epistemology can explain the unique rationality of children, and provide a metaphysical basis for normative behavior. Moreover, it can help us as caregivers better understand and empathize with children, by explaining the similarities and differences between children and adults.
A central part of recent debates in the sociology of childhood has been the division between children as becomings and children as beings. Both positions have been well argued and have had significant impact on everyday teachers’ practice, but still they present diametrically opposite attitudes towards the concept of a child and his/her development. In former view, children are seen as subjects largely without subjectivity and individuality, as a ‘set of potentials’ or a ‘project in making’ which are to develop into adults (beings) or, in other words, that children are in the state of ‘not yet being’. The new perspectives on the concept of children regard children as beings. In this view children are seen as active human beings, who take part in everyday life which is more than just preparation for the future. A child is seen as a social actor and should be understood in its own right and not by assumed shortfall of competence, reason or significance. There is a growing need for a model that can bring these different positions together and make them integrated, interdependent and necessary components of the same field instead of being competitive, in order to better understand the concept of a child and to increase his/her agency in the contemporary world. This paper will examine different constructions of childhood as well as concepts of children as beings and children as becomings and argue for the importance of connecting these two concepts, so that they should not be considered as opposed but rather integrated and complementary. Although they are well-supported, neither being nor becoming discourse on their own provide adequate viewpoint for understanding of children and childhood in the society they live in. Both aspects are interrelated in children’s lives. Furthermore, both views on children and childhood have shortcomings which could be overcome by complementing one with the other. Keywords: childhood, children, beings, becomings
The Paideia Archive: Twentieth Century World Congress of Philosophy 18, 1998: 12-19. , 1998
The Western onto-theological tradition has long been preoccupied with two symbolizations of childhood. One conceives of it as an original unity of being and knowing, an exemplar of completed identity. The other conceives of childhood as deficit and danger, an exemplar of the untamed appetite and the uncontrolled will. In the economy of Plato and Aristotle's tripartite self, the child is ontogenetically out of balance. She is incapable of bringing the three parts of the self into a right hierarchal relation based on the domination of reason. In other words, attaining adulthood means eradicating the child. Freud's reformulation of the Platonic community of self combines the two symbolizations. His model creates an opening for shifting power relations between the elements of the self. He opens the way toward what Kristeva calls the "subject-in-process," a pluralism of relationships rather than an organization constituted by exclusions and hierarchies. After Freud, the child comes to stand for the inexpugnable demands of desire. Through dialogue with this child, the postmodern adult undergoes the dismantling of the notion of subjectivity based on domination, and moves toward the continuous reconstruction of the subject-in-process.
Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 9(1), 1-21, 2015
Traditionally, most philosophers saw childhood as a state of deficiency and thought that its value was entirely dependent on how successfully it prepares individuals for adulthood. Yet, there are good reasons to think that childhood also has intrinsic value. Children possess certain intrinsically valuable abilities to a higher degree than adults. Moreover, going through a phase when one does not yet have a “self of one’s own,” and experimenting one’s way to a stable self, seems intrinsically valuable. I argue that children can have good lives, on several understandings of well-being – as a pleasurable state, as the satisfaction of simple desires or as the realization of certain objective goods. In reply to the likely objection that only individuals capable of morality can have intrinsic value, I explain why it is plausible that children have sufficient moral agency to be as deserving of respect as adults.
Wittgenstein Studien, DOI: 10.1515/witt-2022-0009, 2022
In the sparse literature that is concerned with Wittgenstein's views regarding children and childhood, in his later work, it is often suggested that Wittgenstein presents, or at least is committed to, a romantic notion of the child according to which children should be conceived of as innocent beings who are ontologically different from adults. In this paper I argue that Wittgenstein's remarks do not support such an interpretation. First, I investigate the arguments for this view presented by Stanley Cavell, Yasushi Maruyama, and Philip Shields. Second, I consider an anti-essentialist understanding of Wittgenstein's concept of childhood that has been suggested in opposition to the treatment of the child as the 'ontological other' and argue that Wittgenstein refers to the child as intermediate link with which to state grammatical facts. In contrast to these various views, I hold, third, that the PI is committed to a strong and substantial concept of childhood. I argue for this claim on the basis of (i) the 'Motto' of the PI; (ii) Wittgenstein's reference to the philosopher Augustine; and (iii) the use of 'primitive'. I conclude that Wittgenstein's concept of childhood in his later works neither romanticises nor dispraises the child as the 'ontological other'.
International studies in philosophy, 2002
This paper examines the relationship between Merleau-Ponty's account of our relations with others found in the Phenomenology of Perception and the account he provides in The Child's Relations with Others.
In in Anja Muller, Ed. (2013). Childhood in the English Renaissance, 145-153. Trier: Wissenschaftlicher Verlag Trier, 2013
A discussion of "childhood" as signifier in post-modernity, which draws on the work of Deleuze and Guattari, Lyotard, Marcuse, and the Latin American philosopher of childhood, Walter Kohan.
Kindheit – Bildung – Erziehung. Philosophische Perspektiven, 2021
Bloomsbury History Theory and Method, 2022
Medicine Health Care and Philosophy, 2001
What does a confrontation between philosophy and psychoanalysis look like? My task is a philosophical investigation of a psychoanalytic concept. Thus, I offer a conceptual analysis of a concept that is used both clinically and as a part of a metapsychology. The concept that I investigate in this article is regression. I work with the following two problems: What does a conceptual analysis of the phenomenon called “regression” look like? Regression can be regarded as an instrument that can give us knowledge about ourselves. What does this mean? I compare two ways of analyzing regression, an atomistic as well as an holistic approach. This comparison is made by way of a discussion of the conceptual analysis of the infant. Can we construct the inner life of the infant? How should we conceptualize the primitive? Using concepts like ‘conceptual holism’ and ‘holism of attributes’, I draw parallell conclusions about the construction of the infant's inner life and the analysis of the concept of regression.
2013
Abstract What is it about a person’s becoming an adult that makes it generally inappropriate to treat that person paternalistically? The Standard View holds that a mere difference in age or stage of life cannot in itself be morally relevant. Such chronological characteristics can only matter insofar as they are correlated with the development of capacities for mature practical reasoning. Contrary to the Standard View, I will argue that the young person’s stage of life can in itself be a morally relevant consideration in the justification of paternalism. Thus, two people can have all the same general psychological attributes and yet the mere fact that one person is at the beginning of a life and another in the middle of one can justify treating the younger person more paternalistically than the older one. I claim that recognizing the moral relevance of age is crucial if we want to do justice to both the liberal moral ideal of respect for autonomy and our demanding educational aims, given that these otherwise come into conflict with one another (a problem I call the “Dilemma of Liberal Education”). Another major virtue of recognizing the moral relevance of stage of life is that we can see one reason why adults with cognitive disabilities should not be treated like children.
The Journal of Value Inquiry, 2021
Some philosophers argue that childhood is a predicament, a condition that is significantly worse than adulthood. Others argue that childhood is a blessing and might be equal or superior in value to adulthood. We present several thought experiments that challenge both these views. These hypothetical cases support neither the claim that childhood is better than adulthood, the claim that adulthood is better than childhood, the claim that childhood and adulthood have equal value, nor the claim that their values are incommensurable. We are then left with a vacuum to fill. After rejecting one initially appealing theory (‘the Diversity View’) that aims to explain our intuitions regarding the aforementioned cases, we propose what will be referred to as the Development View, according to which what is good is for humans to develop from childhood into adulthood at a certain pace.
Philosophy Compass, 2021
In philosophy, there are two competitor views about the nature and value of childhood: The first is the traditional, deficiency, view, according to which children are mere unfinished adults. The second is a view that has recently become increasingly popular amongst philosophers, and according to which children, perhaps in virtue of their biological features, have special and valuable capacities, and, more generally, privileged access to some sources of value. This article provides a conceptual map of these views and their possible interpretations, and notes their bearing on issues of population ethics and on the duties that we are owed during childhood.
2012
Alongside the child’s need “to become,” to develop and change, to fulfill dreams and plans, there is another need. This is the child’s need to be his authentic self and to be recognized as “somebody” when simply being that self. A children’s rights regime should ideally be responsive to the complementary needs “to be” and the need “to become” within the right to identity. Granting the right to autonomy, responding to the child’s need “to become,” and overcoming adult paternalism is often perceived as the most advanced and most problematic stage in the evolution of child law. This perception is misleading. The need to be one’s self is sometimes neglected by advocates of children’s rights, though it is well embedded in social science literature. It is suggested that this is because of Western culture’s preoccupation with material progress. In order for the child to fulfill his unique human potential, to arise to a supra animal motivation when exercising his rights, we must offer the c...
For the Western adult, separated from childhood by the cultural and psychological "coming of age" of modernism, childhood is a once-familiar text become strange, which can only be reapropriated through dialogue, both with real children and with the "child within." In the Western iconography of self, childhood has come to represent an end point, a spiritual goal of unity with self and world, a reappropriation of nature and the unconscious of which the experience of childhood itself is not so much exemplary as prophetic. The reappropriation of childhood is thus a dialectical one, of which the journey into alienation represented by adulthood is a necessary moment. Thus childhood occupies a central place in the Western mythology of self, which is construed as a voyage out of unity into multiplicity, and toward a unity painfully regained on a higher level. The implicit telos of this historical myth is the end of history, for it is repression, division, and self-alienation which generate historical time, and the utopia of a recovered childhood, in recovering the primary narcissism of the childhood experience, passes beyond repression to the "heaven" of instinctual liberation.
Journal of Philosophy of Education, 2015
This article begins with the question: What is it to live? It is argued that, from a Spinozistic perspective, to live is not an either/or kind of matter. Rather, it is something that inevitably comes in degrees. The idea is that through good education and proper training a person can learn to increase his or her degree of existence by acquiring more adequate (as opposed to confused) ideas. This gradual qualitative enhancement of existence is an operationalization of Spinoza's quest for immortality of the mind. While Spinoza's idea of immortality differs from the traditional Christian account of the immortality of the soul in some key respects, it nevertheless concerns a form of immortality of the mind albeit grasped from a strictly naturalistic standpoint. And as such it is clear that we are faced with not only a philosophical and metaphysical problem of some magnitude but that we have come up against an educational problem that is rarely addressed. The educational problem, emanating from this, concerns the tension between Spinoza's necessitarianism and the overall goal of education. Why educate people at all if their lives are already predetermined? In addressing these problems, this article marks an attempt to present a pedagogization of the degrees of existence in Spinoza. To this end, it is argued that (1) the imitation of affects is key to understanding Spinoza in an educational setting and; (2) that teaching, in a Spinozistic context, involves the act of offering the right amount of resistance.
Journal of Applied Philosophy, 2018
Children and childhood have been largely ignored by philosophers outside the philosophy of education. Recently this has started to change. In particular, the past few decades have seen a growing interest in children as subjects of political philosophy, with a focus on questions concerning duties of justice towards children and especially parental duties, as well as parental rights and filial duties. Most of the current debates rest on more foundational positions about the nature and value of childhood, issues that are not normally given the same scrutiny. The purpose of this symposium is to examine precisely these foundational questions.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.