Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences
Embryos have different meanings for different people and in different contexts. Seen under the microscope, the biological embryo starts out as one cell and then becomes a bunch of cells. Gradually these divide and differentiate to make up the embryo, which in humans becomes a fetus at eight weeks, and then eventually a baby. At least, that happens in those cases that carry through normally and successfully. Yet a popular public perception imagines the embryo as already a little person in the very earliest stages of development, as if it were predictably to become an adult. In actuality, cells can combine, pull apart, and recombine in a variety of ways and still produce embryos, whereas most embryos never develop into adults at all. Biological embryos and popular imaginations of embryos diverge. This paper looks at some of the historical reasons for and social implications of that divergence.
Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences, 2015
South Dakota Medicine, 2023
The human embryo is dimensionally complex. As the details of its developmental biology and pathobiology became more established, widely divergent concepts about the embryo emerged in culture, religion, morals, ethics, and law1 and today underlie worldwide controversies about the very meaning of human life. Our investigation began with our belief that historical research into the evolution of our biological and philosophical understanding of the embryo could provide a basis for approaching those controversies. We hypothesized that scientific understandings of conception and fetal development historically influenced the social, cultural, philosophical and legal status of the embryo. We explored the conceptual divergence between embryology and philosophical domains that began in the Renaissance. We confined ourselves to embryology within western civilizations and philosophical and theological doctrine from a predominantly Christian perspective.
Science & Education, 2013
It might seem that an embryo is an embryo, and that there would be a fact of the matter. That seems especially true with respect to the way embryos are presented in textbooks, including high school biology textbooks. This paper looks at three co-existing, competing, and often conflicting views of embryos. Then with a close study of twentieth century high school biology textbooks, it explores suggestions about the ways those books have influenced public impressions of embryos.
Cherionna Menzam-Sills, 2023
Findings in the field of pre-and perinatal psychology reveal that, even as little embryos, we are having experiences, and that these experiences profoundly affect how we live our lives 1. Our earliest days establish lifelong tendencies influencing how we connect with ourselves, each other, and our planet. 2 This paper examines the intersection of embryo and psyche, how development of one relates to development of the other. Evidence of cellular intelligence, responsiveness, memory, and learning is offered as a foundation for understanding the profound effects of very early experience. 3,4 Specific developmental milestones of conception, implantation, and discovery are considered in relation to their psychological effects, underlining the importance of treating the embryo as a sentient, sensitive human being that both models and thrives on love and connection 5. It is proposed that supporting new parents from the time of pre-conception in providing a welcoming, safe, loving environment for their baby contributes to a world characterized by these qualities, where we can return to our original potential.
Journal of the History of Biology, 2010
This essay describes the approach and early results of the collaborative Embryo Project and its on-line encyclopedia (http://embryo.asu.edu). The project is based on a relational database that allows federated searches and inclusion of multiple types of objects targeted for multiple user groups. The emphasis is on the history and varied contexts of developmental biology, focusing on people, places, institutions, techniques, literature, images, and other aspects of study of embryos. This essay introduces the ways of working as well as the long-term goals of the project. We invite others to join the effort, both in this particular project and in joining together in digital collection, archiving, and knowledge generation at the borders of biology and history.
2010
Public attention on embryo research has never been greater. Modern reproductive medicine technology and the use of embryos to generate stem cells ensure that this will continue to be a topic of debate and research across many disciplines. This multidisciplinary book explores the concept of a 'healthy' embryo, its implications on the health of children and adults, and how perceptions
European Journal of Endocrinology, 2004
The moral acceptability or non-acceptability of the use of human embryos in research raises questions on several philosophical levels. The mixing-up of these levels results in strongly defended and endless debates. In this contribution, arguments on three levels will be discussed, the ontological, the practical and instrumental and the level of human relationships. It is concluded that, on the latter level, the moral problems of the other two are significant, but not conclusive. The decision to allow or to ban research with human embryos is charged with full human responsibility.
New Genetics and …, 2008
In this paper we offer some reflections on embryos in the biomedical worlds of embryonic stem cells (ESC) and pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD). We draw upon two ethnographic studies of the social practices of PGD and embryonic stem cell science to ...
Austin Journal of Anatomy, 2024
Embryogenesis, the process of human development from fertilization to birth, involves several stages such as the formation of bones, muscles, and facial features, which modern science has detailed. Remarkably, the Quran described many of these stages over 1,400 years ago. The Quran accurately identifies the male sperm as determining the baby’s sex, describes the development of the embryo in stages, and mentions the fetus being protected in “a triple darkness,” referring to the layers surrounding it. The Quran also touches on the changes in the womb lining, the protective amniotic fluid, and the formation of bones and muscles, all of which align with modern scientific findings. This shows a striking harmony between ancient scripture and contemporary embryology.
From the time that James Thomson and colleagues (1998) fi rst announced the successful derivation of human embryonic stem cell (hESC) lines, there has been a heated debate about the ethical acceptability of hESC research because this research entails the destruction of human embryos (see Prainsack et al., 2008a). In an effort to quell this debate, governments, quasi-governmental organizations, and professional organizations around the world have sought to develop ethical standards for embryo research and hESC research, and to entrench these standards in laws or research guidelines. Together, these many and varied ethical and legal standards for embryo research and hESC research currently shape the fi eld of stem cell science. Their importance can be measured by the fact that scientists consider these standards In an effort to quell ongoing debate about the ethics of human embryonic stem cell (hESC) research, there have been concerted efforts to develop ethical standards for both emb...
Journal of applied philosophy, 2001
Journal of Applied Philosophy, 2001
One strategy for arguing that it should be legally permissible to create human embryos, or to use of spare human embryos, for scientific research purposes involves the claim that such embryos cannot be persons because they are not human individuals while twinning may yet take place. Being a human individual is considered to be by most people a necessary condition for being a human person. I argue first that such an argument against the personhood of embryos must be rationally conclusive if their destruction in public places such as laboratories is to be countenanced. I base this argument on a popular understanding of the role that the notion of privacy plays in abortion law. I then argue that such arguments against personhood are not rationally conclusive. The claim that the early embryos is not a human individual is not nearly as obvious as some assert.
Law and Biomedicine, 2022
From a critical human rights-based approach, Law and Biomedicine addresses available international legal answers to various questions about human life and health affecting highly appreciated individual and social values—namely, autonomy, life, dignity, and moral status, among others. Papers of each lesson are available under request.
Over the last several decades many abortion advocates have attempted to spread confusion and doubt concerning the beginnings of human life. A particularly cynical strategy has involved invoking the authority historical thinkers, especially Doctors of the Church, to support the claim that (at least) early abortion does not constitute homicide because the early embryo is not yet fully human. Anyone familiar with context of these historical thinkers should realize that their specific judgments regarding abortion are now obsolete in virtue of their primitive scientific understanding of embryology. In what follows, I summarize the Aristotelian embryology that explains why these historical thinkers held the views that they did. I then explore how we should best understand their broader ethical views in light of our vastly superior contemporary knowledge of human embryology. Unsurprisingly, it turns out that if we apply the contemporary empirical findings of embryology the very same metaphysical and ethical principles informing the thinking of the historical figures supports the prolife position.
Birth Defects Research Part C: Embryo Today: Reviews, 2008
The following essay was delivered at the conference ''Ontogeny and Human Life'' at the Ponifical Athenaeum ''Regina Apostolorum,'' November, 2007. Sponsored by the Legion of Christ, the Pontifical Academy for Life, and the John Templeton Foundation, the sessions focused on when the conceptus became a ''person.'' My essay focused on the scientific conclusions that could aid such discussions. Moreover, after listening to the philosophical, legal, and theological discussions that ensued, I responded theologically as well. New concepts in modern embryology have made scientists revise their views concerning the autonomy of embryos and the mechanisms that generate such embryos. There are interactions between the sperm and the female reproductive tract and egg which had never been known until recently. There are also interactions between the developing organism and its environment that had been unsuspected a decade ago. Gut bacteria induce the development of the mammalian digestive system and immune system by changing the gene expression patterns in the mammalian intestine. Conversely, chemicals in our technological society can adversely affect the embryo, rendering it sterile or prone to tumors later in life. While there is no consensus among scientists as to when human life begins, both Church and science can become allies in persuading governments to regulate or ban the production and use of these fetotoxic chemicals. These new views of embryonic development change many of the stories told about human embryos and fetuses, and they have implications concerning the use of science as evidence for theological positions.
“Embryos in the Early Modern and Modern Periods: A Visual Dialogue,” The Healthy Embryo, ed. Jeff Nisker et. al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 97-115.
This paper analyzes the transformation from the human zygote to the implanted embryo under the prism of substantial change. After a brief introduction, it vindicates the Aristotelian ideas of substance and accident, and those of substantial and accidental change. It then claims that the transformation from the multicelled zygote to the implanted embryo amounts to a substantial change. Pushing further, it contends that this substantial change cannot be explained following patterns of genetic reductionism, emergence, and self-organization, and proposes Gustavo Bueno's idea of anamorphosis as a means to encapsulate criticism against such positions.
In this article, I argue in favor of the moral permissibility of using surplus embryos (embryos leftover from fertility treatments) for human embryonic stem cell research. I will begin with a metaphysical argument: human blastocysts cannot be regarded as the beginning stages of an individual human life because fully developed human beings and blastocysts do not share an essential property-individuality. Because human beings are essentially individuals, and because human blastocysts are not, there can be no identity relation between them. Second, I argue that, even if we grant embryos the status of persons for the sake of argument, this does not necessarily entail the moral impermissibility of embryonic stem cell research since an extrauterine embryo cannot be given a right to compel others to gestate it, given that no person has a right to force others to undergo forced bodily intrusion as a method of sustenance. This makes the demise of these embryos inevitable, unless their respective genetic mother chooses to gestate (although embryo adoption is being compelled in at least one state as an alternative to destruction). Finally, given their destruction, I argue that using these embryos for research purposes illustrates a far more respectful attitude than destroying them in fertility clinics.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.