Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2010, Philosophic Exchange
Our lives intertwine with praise and blame in ways both simple and complex. If you ask me to pick up your child after work, and I fail to do so even after promising that I would, you will very likely be angry at me. This is not the irritation we experience when the weather is chilly or when we don't win the lottery. This attitude is directed at a specific person, ordinarily a (somewhat) aware and responsive being. That is, you are presuming that I am a particular kind of entity, a responsive, choice-making agent. It is partly in virtue of this fact that your reaction of irritation has its distinctive flavor; unlike bad weather or unreliable lottery drawings, I can knowingly and willingly bind myself with commitments that we both take to license blaming when I fail to live up to them. In short, I am a special kind of entity-a responsible agent. In virtue of my conduct, I can be worthy of praise and blame. These moralized reactions are not limited to interpersonal relationships. People spend years in prison, beyond what is plausibly useful for rehabilitation, and usually to the exclusion of victim restitution, out of an oftentimes inchoate or implicit conviction that criminals deserve punishment in light of their culpable failure to exercise their agency in the right ways. Indeed, it is difficult to make sense of the impulse to execute criminals without appeal to some notion of deservingness bound up in the idea that the criminal is morally responsible for his crime in some deep way. So, moral responsibility, the idea of praiseworthiness, blameworthiness, and associated notions of merit are all important parts of our shared lives. This picture, however, is threatened by a very familiar chain of reasoning. The reasoning goes like this: if everything is caused, no one is genuinely free, and thus, no one can be genuinely morally responsible for anything. It is a very old argument. 1 Versions of it have been banging around in the Western intellectual tradition for millennia, and every age has its favorite formulation of it. Perhaps the most common contemporary incarnation of
Some writers, such as John Fischer and Michael McKenna, have recently claimed that an agent can be morally responsible for a wrong action and yet not be blameworthy for that action. A careful examination of the claim, however, suggests two readings. On one reading, there are further conditions on blameworthiness beyond freely and wittingly doing wrong. On another innocuous reading, there are no such further conditions. Despite Fischer and McKenna's attempts to offer further conditions on blameworthiness in addition to responsibility for wrongdoing, I argue that only the innocuous reading is plausible. Once we distinguish between blame being deserved and blame being all-things-considered appropriate, we need not appeal to further conditions on blameworthiness. This discussion has important upshots regarding how compatibilists respond to certain manipulation arguments and how proponents of derived responsibility respond to criticism that agents are responsible even for outcomes that are not reasonably foreseeable.
Some sort of freedom is a pre-condition for moral responsibility. If we are not free in some such fundamental way, then moral responsibility is unintelligible and its associated categories become inapplicable or dispensable. Not all sorts of practices become dispensable when their key concepts become unintelligible. Arguably, there may be good reasons to keep practices of holding each other responsible even when the pre-conditions of applicability of their key concepts have been denied. The issue of dispensability of concepts may be not thoroughly or completely conceptual; that is, it may be determined by considerations that have nothing to do with the nature of concepts. But I will not be concerned with such external considerations. I am interested in elucidating the concept of moral responsibility, where an agent is responsible for x if he is appropriately held accountable and it is answerable for x.
: This article sets out a notion of moral responsibility that incorporates the central features of the answerability conception advocated by T. M Scanlon, Hilary Bok, and Angela Smith, and of Michael McKenna’s more specific conversational account, but which excludes any notion of desert, whether basic or non-basic. The point of blaming and praising on this notion largely forward-looking: its main objectives are protection, reconciliation, and moral formation. Agents are blameworthy and praiseworthy by virtue of being appropriate recipients of blame and praise given these aims. Blaming on this conception can involve causing harm, but the justifiability of such harming does not reintroduce the legitimacy of desert. The resulting notion of moral responsibility is immune to any threat from the causal determination of action.
Philosophy Compass, Vol. 7, No. 3, 2012
Blame is usually discussed in the context of the free will problem, but recently moral philosophers have begun to examine it on its own terms. If, as many suppose, free will is to be understood as the control relevant to moral responsibility, and moral responsibility is to be understood in terms of whether blame is appropriate, then an independent inquiry into the nature and ethics of blame will be essential to solving (and, perhaps, even fully understanding) the free will problem. In this article we first survey and categorize recent accounts of the nature of blame – is it action, belief, emotion, desire, or something else? – and then we look at several proposed requirements on appropriate blame that look beyond the transgressor himself, considerations that will form part of a full account of the ethics of blame.
Blame: Its Nature and Norms, edited by D. Justin Coates and Neal A. Tognazzini, is a vital resource for those interested in moral responsibility, especially its normative aspects. The book includes fourteen new essays-all of excellent quality-as well as a valuable and substantial introductory essay, "The Contours of Blame," by the editors.
Philosophy Compass, 2007
In this article I examine the relation between causation and moral responsibility. I distinguish four possible views about that relation. One is the standard view: the view that an agent's moral responsibility for an outcome requires, and is grounded in, the agent's causal responsibility for it. I discuss several challenges to the standard view, which motivate the three remaining views. The final viewthe view I argue for -is that causation is the vehicle of transmission of moral responsibility. According to this view, although moral responsibility does not require causation, causation still grounds moral responsibility.
Philosophical Psychology, 2021
Why do we find agents less blameworthy when they face mitigating circumstances, and what does this show about philosophical theories of moral responsibility? We present novel evidence that the tendency to mitigate the blameworthiness of agents is driven both by the perception that they are less normatively competent—in particular, less able to know that what they are doing is wrong—and by the perception that their behavior is less attributable to their deep selves. Consequently, we argue that philosophers cannot rely on the case strategy to support the Normative Competence theory of moral responsibility over the Deep Self theory. However, we also outline ways in which further empirical and philosophical work would shift the debate, by showing that there is a significant departure between ordinary concepts and corresponding philosophical concepts, or by focusing on a different type of coherence with ordinary judgments.
University of San Francisco law review, 2016
BLAMEWORTHINESS, OR CULPABILITY, IS CENTRAL TO THE LAW, to morality, and, generally, to many social norms. Other than for consensual obligations, such as contracts, a common intuition is that a person should not be liable for harms caused to another person or to the state if she has not engaged in blameworthy conduct. Furthermore, if a person does harm another through blameworthy conduct, the intuition often extends to the belief that the degree of culpability should be a factor in gauging a just requital.1 Malicious homicide, for instance, deserves greater punishment than negligent homicide does, and an intentional battery should occasion a more extensive liability than a comparable negligent injury. While there may be proper arenas for strict liability, typically it is applied only for substantial reasons that trump the common urge to free a person from responsibility to others for the consequences of her conduct that was reasonable and not culpable.2 Even utilitarians, who champi...
European Public Law, 2012
Journal of Experimental Social …, 2003
doctoral dissertation, 2013
What We Owe to Each Other Thomas Scanlon distinguished two senses of responsibility, substantive responsibility and responsibility as attributability and provided a nuanced description and analysis of both concepts. Elaborating on the latter notion in a series of articles Angela Smith developed a unified account of attributonism, the "rational relations view". According to Neil Levy's formulation, "on the attributionist account, I am responsible for my attitudes, and my acts and omissions insofar as they express my attitudes, in all cases in which my attributes express my identity as a practical agent. Attitudes are thus expressive of who I am if they belong to the class of judgment-sensitive attitudes" (Levy 2005).
Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 2015
According to the conventional view, causal and moral responsibility have a strict hierarchical relationship. Determining causal responsibility comes first; then we sort through the factors to which we have assigned causal responsibility and determine which, if any, should be assigned moral responsibility too. Moral inquiry accordingly stands not only apart but also above causal inquiry. But I am going to argue that this way of looking at causal and moral responsibility is a mistake. Rather than being separate and independent inquires with different purposes and concerns, I am going to argue that finding causal responsibility actually entails finding moral responsibility even when there is no evidence of what we would call traditional fault. Indeed, I am going to argue we cannot find someone causally responsible without finding them morally responsible too.
Public Affairs Quarterly, 2020
Control accounts of moral responsibility argue that agents must possess certain capacities in order to be blameworthy for wrongdoing. This is sometimes thought to be revisionary, because reflection on our moral practices reveals that we often blame many agents who lack these capacities. This paper argues that Control accounts of moral responsibility are not too revisionary, nor too permissive, because they can still demand quite a lot from excused wrongdoers. Excused wrongdoers can acquire duties of reconciliation, which require that they improve themselves, make reparations for the harm caused, and retract the meaning expressed in the original wrong. Failure to do these things expresses a lack of regard for the victims, and can make those wrongdoers appropriate targets of blame.
In this paper it is argued that we can have defensible attributions of responsibility without first answering the question whether determinism and free will are compatible. The key to such a defense is a focus on the fact that most actions for which we hold one another responsible are quite ordinary—trespassing traffic regulations, tardiness, or breaking a promise. As we will show, unlike actions that problematize our moral competence — e.g. akratic and ‘moral monster’- like ones—ordinary ‘wrong’ actions often disclose this competence. Hence, no counterfactual assumption is needed to establish that some of us are sometimes responsible for some of the actions we perform.
Philosophical Studies, 2019
P.F. Strawson's compatibilism about free will and his attendant account of moral responsibility have had a considerable influence on contemporary work. 2 This is so even among those who do not count themselves as followers of Strawson's overall compatibilist program. Even opponents address Strawson's main themes: the moral emotions and our practices of interpersonal expectations and demands. 3 Despite this influence, there are two damning problems for Strawson's theory. First, it appears to restrict the class of morally responsible agents to those who are in fact members of the moral community. However, as Gary Watson has argued in "Responsibility and the Limits of Evil" (2008/1987), this has a disturbing consequence: extreme evil exempts an agent from moral responsibility. If so, why shouldn't we view this as a reductio? Second, in some cases our emotional reaction to an evildoer's history clashes with our emotional expressions of blame. We might then worry that anyone's actions can be explained by his or her history, and thereby, conflict with our present blame. We might also worry that had our history been like the unfortunate evildoer, we too might have been evil. This compromises our standing to blame. Together, this would undermine the expression of blame, generally, and so be self-defeating. It is critical to the Strawsonian project to respond to these problems. I will do so in a novel way. As I see it, we have an impoverished vocabulary of reactive attitudes. Expanding our vocabulary can dissolve the problems. To do so, I will
Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy
This paper takes up the question of whether the consequences of a person’s volitional actions can contribute to their blameworthiness. On the one hand it is intuitively plausible to hold that if D1 volitionally shoots V with the intention of killing V then D1 is blameworthy for V’s death. On the other hand, if the only difference between D1 and D2 is resultant luck, many find it counter-intuitive to hold that D1 is more blameworthy than D2. There are three broad (non-skeptical) strategies for resolving this tension: accept resultant moral luck, deny that one can be morally responsible for outcomes, or accept that outcomes can be within the scope of things one is morally responsible for while denying that they can affect the degree of blameworthiness. This paper aims to defend resultant moral luck against both the scoping and the internalist strategies by drawing on an “inclusive conception” of blameworthiness, according to which how much blame one deserves is a function of two i...
Inquiry, 2015
Philosophers have been concerned with and puzzled by the nature of responsibility at least since Aristotle's time. What does it take to be a responsible agent? Under what conditions is it justifiable to hold someone responsible for her character or behavior? Notoriously, it seems to many that genuine responsibility requires a kind of metaphysical freedom that is hard to understand much less believe in, while others insist that no such metaphysical freedom is necessary. A common way of introducing the subject calls attention to two senses of responsibility. Sometimes when we say "X is responsible for Y' we mean only to name a causal connection: X is an individual or a state of affairs that makes a salient causal contribution to the occurrence of Y. In this sense, your cat might be responsible for the spilled milk, the rain might be responsible for spoiling the picnic. By contrast, this paradigmatic introduction continues, when we charge an individual with moral responsibility, we mean something more. Like the cat, a person can be causally responsible for the spilled milk if she knocks over the bottle during an epileptic seizure; like the rain, a person can be causally responsible for spoiling the picnic if in the course of it she is stung by a bee and goes into anaphylactic shock. But a person might also spill the milk on purpose, wanting to ruin her host's tablecloth or disrupt the family brunch; she might spoil the picnic by her irritable carping or by rudely insulting the other guests. In these latter cases the person's connection to the event under discussion appears to reflect more deeply on her, and, at least initially, it does not seem inappropriate to blame her. These latter cases
Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility, ed. Andreas Brekke, Cambridge UP, 2022
Central cases of moral blame suggest that blame presupposes that its target deserves to feel guilty, and that if one is blameworthy to some degree, one deserves to feel guilt to a corresponding degree. This, some think, is what explains why being blameworthy for something presupposes having had a strong kind of control over it: only given such control is the suffering involved in feeling guilt deserved. This chapter argues that all this is wrong. As evidenced by a wider range of cases, blame doesn’t presuppose that the target deserves to feel guilt and doesn’t necessarily aim at the target’s suffering in recognition of what they have done. On the constructive side, the chapter offers an explanation of why, in many cases of moral blameworthiness, the agent nevertheless does deserve to feel guilt. The explanation leans on a general account of moral and non-moral blame and blameworthiness and a version of the popular idea that moral blame targets agents’ objectionable quality of will. Given the latter idea, the morally blameworthy have harmed the standing of some person or value, giving rise to obligations to give correspondingly less relative weight to their own standing, and so, sometimes, to their own suffering.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.