Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2021, Dise, Michael. "The Act of Omnipotence: Abolition of the Mystical Quest." In D. G. Leahy and the Thinking Now Occurring, edited by Lissa McCullough and Elliot Wolfson. New York: State University of New York Press.
…
23 pages
1 file
In the classical theological paradigm divine omnipotence is absolutely constricted by the goal intrinsic to God’s own Plan or Nature: the goal is an absolute union in which God knows Godself in relation to an individual via a creature belonging to the Creator as the latter’s own property/self-expression. Here the divine Self-expression is the limit to actual novelty in the Godhead in essence. From the creature’s end this union is pursued through the negation of finite particularity insofar as it opposes realization of the universal Self. But in the new conception of omnipotence both Creator and creature are absolutely free via the transcendence of the goal: the Creator without a prior plan whose nature is simply to create ex nihilo demonstrates omnipotence in the act of creating an absolute Other with whom the Creator remains absolutely intimate while ceasing absolutely from sovereignty over that Other’s existence: here omnipotence moves to new ground where the Creator as such shares its essence with the creature absolutely qua incarnation. The lasting fruit of this absolutely efficacious ceasing/giving is the infinite transaction of infinite Others building up a new creation that absolutely transfigures the Godhead into the Absolute Body of Christ. This essentially new unity is the Apocalyptic Body of God now beginning in an essentially new form of thinking: what D.G. Leahy calls the thinking now occurring for the first time in history (TNO) which is the new world consciousness of a new world order.
God's Omnipotence, 2024
This paper explores the divine attribute of omnipotence in Christian theology, focusing on the contrasting views of Thomas Aquinas and Jürgen Moltmann. While Aquinas presents God’s omnipotence as consistent with His perfect nature, unable to act contrary to His goodness, Moltmann reimagines omnipotence through God’s participation in human suffering, particularly in the crucifixion. The paper critiques both approaches, proposing a synthesis that balances God’s self-limiting love with His ultimate sovereignty, emphasizing that God’s omnipotence must reconcile logical coherence with human suffering. This synthesis offers a more nuanced and pastorally compassionate understanding of divine power.
Religious Studies, 2012
An omnipotent being would be a being whose power was unlimited. The power of human beings is limited in two distinct ways: we are limited with respect to our freedom of will, and we are limited in our ability to execute what we have willed. These two distinct sources of limitation suggest a simple definition of omnipotence: an omnipotent being is one that has both perfect freedom of will and perfect efficacy of will. In this article we further explicate this definition and show that it escapes the standard objections to divine omnipotence. (2012) 48, 403-414
The Heythrop Journal, 2001
Philosophical debate about the problem of evil derives, in part, from differing definitions of omnipotence. Philosophical theists like Thomas Aquinas, Terence Penelhum, Alvin Plantinga and John Hick attribute evil in the world to the uncoerced acts of free agents. On this Christian account, God is not responsible for evil, for even an all-powerful or omnipotent God could not create free agents who were forced to be good. Adam and Eve and their progeny, in choosing of their own free will to participate in evil, have brought suffering into the world. Modern atheists such as John McTaggart, J. L. Mackie, Earl Conee and Danny Goldstick propose a radically different concept of omnipotence. They maintain that an omnipotent God must be able to accomplish anything, even if it entails a contradiction. On this account, God possesses absolute or radical omnipotence. The Christian God cannot be both omnipotent and benevolent, for a benevolent, omnipotent God would have forced free agents to desist from evil and prevented the introduction of suffering into the world. If the task of creating free agents that are forced to be good entails a contradiction, this is of little consequence, for a God who is truly omnipotent can perform contradictory feats. In this article, I argue that the atheistic tradition is mistaken. Firstly, the concept of absolute omnipotence does not present an obstacle to belief in a benevolent God. Even an absolutely omnipotent God could, as an act of benevolence, create a world in which there is suffering. Secondly, I argue, in line with theological and philosophical tradition, that the concept of absolute omnipotence is fatally flawed. A God who was able to violate the laws of logic would be less than all-powerful. He would be weak rather than strong. So the atheist's argument fails when it is carefully considered on its own terms and when it is evaluated in the light of a more rational account of omnipotence.
Faith and Philosophy, 2000
One of the cornerstones of western theology is the doctrine of divine omnipotence. God is traditionally conceived of as an omnipotent or all-powerful being. However, satisfactory analyses of omnipotence are notoriously elusive. In this paper, I first consider some simple attempts to analyze omnipotence, showing how each fails. I then consider two more sophisticated accounts of omnipotence. The first of these is presented by Edward Wierenga; the second by Thomas Flint and Alfred Freddoso. I argue that both of these accounts fail. Finally, I propose and defend a novel account of omnipotence.
Religious Studies, 2012
The notion of omnipotence has proved to be quite recalcitrant to analysis. Still, during the last three decades or so, there has resurfaced a clever argument to the effect that, whatever omnipotence is, it cannot be exemplified in God: an allegedly impeccable and all-perfect being. Scrutinizing this argument, however, I find it less than convincing. Moreover, and more importantly, I venture a positive account of my own: a non-technical and distinctively metaphysical definition of omnipotence which, if true, sidesteps quite a number of well-known pitfalls. Also, by way of introduction, I review some earlier attempts.
January , 2022
The omnipotence of God can be defined as the perfect ability of God to do all things that are consistent with the divine character. Open theists see God as one who is influenced as God interacts with human beings in time and space (temporally). Thus, for Open Theists, God is affected and influenced by the world. This paper revisits the historical, biblical and theological grounds for the doctrine of omnipotence with the aim of re-establishing the relevance of divine omnipotence. Using a literary investigation this article traces the developments of the doctrine of God's power from the Early Church Fathers to the Reformers to establish whether the articulation of God's power within Open Theism resonates with Orthodox Theology and Evangelicalism.
This paper develops a simple and attractive account of the traditional divine attribute of omnipotence which makes available equally attractive resolutions of two difficult puzzles in philosophical theology concerning the compatibility of traditional divine attributes. The first puzzle concerns the compatibility of the attributes of omnipotence and perfect goodness, while the second puzzle concerns the compatibility of perfect goodness and freedom. The account of omnipotence here developed is sufficiently plausible and sufficiently different from other competing contemporary accounts of this attribute to merit attention on its own; but, it is even more deserving of attention given the unique resolutions of the aforementioned puzzles it makes available.
In this paper presentation, I try to resolve two paradoxes involving our intuitions concerning omnipotence: The paradox of the stone and the conjunction of the Incarnation with omnipotence. I hypothesize that joining God's omnipotence and His perfect moral character will grant us a beginning strategy for resolving both. This paper has been updated to reflect questions and comments I received at ETS.
2005
I shall begin by criticising the two most promising extant accounts of omnipotence . After providing various reasons for finding these accounts unsatisfactory, I shall then go on to make some suggestions about how the notion of omnipotence should be understood.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
Issues in Science and Theology: Nature – and Beyond. Issues in Science and Religion: Publications of the European Society for the Study of Science and Theology, vol 5, 2020
Reviews in Religion & Theology, 2009
2018
European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 2012
Sophia, 2017
Proceedings of Conferences on the Dialogue between Science and Theology
Modern Theology, 2003
Journal of the European Economic Association, 1996
Thesis, 2018
The Master‟ s Seminary Journal, 2001
Claritas Journal of Dialogue and Culture, 2015
Religious Studies Review, 2007
Nova et Vetera (English Edition), 2016
Logic and Logical Philosophy, 2013