Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2008, HUME'S PROBLEMS WITH INDUCTION
…
188 pages
1 file
HUME'S PROBLEMS WITH INDUCTION is intended to describe and refute some of the main doubts and objections David Hume raised with regard to inductive reasoning. It replaces the so-called problem of induction with a principle of induction.
Hume Studies, 1977
The Heythrop Journal, 2013
This article is a section drawn from a wider study (still in progress) on David Hume's epistemology. Its chapter on induction contains an argument against Hume's critique of this intellectual process that is different than any I have come across in my researches. The closest would be Peter J. R. Millican's article 'Hume, Induction and Reason' wherein he charges Hume for holding 'apparently contradictory positions which he appears to adopt in different places' and specifically notes how 'Hume argues, forcefully and repeatedly, that 'we have no reason' whatever to make inductive inferences; while on the other he continues to make such inferences himself, treats them as varying in force, presents rules for assessing them, describes some as 'just' and 'true', and criticizes natural theologians and others (including 'the vulgar') for failing to conform to the appropriate standards.' 1 Certain of what Millican writes could have led on to make the point of this article, but he does not take it there. The bulk of his article attempts to resolve Hume's induction problem by identifying three different notion of 'reason' as used by Hume. My approach is more straightforward-analyzing how Hume's argument against induction results in a self-defeating conclusion. As the larger study is still at least a year away from completion, I make this part available separately for those interested in this issue. * * * If one were to draw an arch of the major parts of Hume's epistemological theory, without question his antithetical position on induction would be the keystone of the entire design. Hume's dispute with the psychological and epistemological knowledge theories of his predecessors is made especially acute by his critique of the very kind of methodology advanced by many of them, including his philosophical forebear Francis Bacon, for the gaining of scientific understanding-the process of induction. According to the author of The Great Instauration, it was through induction that advances in learning such as the re-charting of the universe 2 from a geocentric to a heliocentric one were brought about. This postulation of Copernicus was expanded and corrected in suite by the laws of motion of Kepler and those of Galileo, Bacon's close contemporary, culminating in the theory of gravity of Isaac Newton about a half-century after Bacon's passing. Bacon's analysis as to how induction ensues within the investigative mind is open to serious question, but his overall trust in its final outcomes would have been amply rewarded by the future discoveries of persons like Newton although many of his arguments are also deductive in nature, a process which Bacon tended to disparage. Truth to tell, in any extensive theoretical system, induction and deduction are both used as inferential tools. Such matters not withstanding, science was clearly on a roll. Hume, oddly enough, does not join the bandwagon but rather raises serious objections not only as to the certitude of the natural laws bs_bs_banner
2012
Hume’s problem of induction has played a major role in modern epistemology and in the philosophy of science. It has provided an inspiration for various philosophers who intend to refute the allegedly skeptical conclusion included in the Hume’s works. Interestingly, though, in contemporary Hume research the claim that Hume was skeptical about induction is vigorously challenged. It is claimed that he meant his argument to be only an explanation of causes of our inductive reasoning. Hume appears to be, on that reading, a kind of naturalistic epistemologist who inquired into the mechanisms of our inductive reasoning. He assumed that some mechanisms of our mind are producing beliefs about causal links and he posed the question: how do we come to have that kind of beliefs? What is the source of our beliefs about causal links? His research led him to discover that the beliefs about causal links are not determined by any piece of abstract reasoning but by nature, custom and imagination. It ...
Synthese, 1998
This paper presents a new account of Hume’s “probability of causes”. There are two main results attained in this investigation. The first, and perhaps the most significant, is that Hume developed – albeit informally – an essentially sound system of probabilistic inductive logic that turns out to be a powerful forerunner of Carnap’s systems. The Humean set of principles include,
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, eds M. Bruce and S. Barbone, Blackwell, 2011
Philosophy, 2002
Synthese 85 (1990): 95-114, 1990
Philosophy of Science, 2010
Hume Studies, 1992
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 2006
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1962
HUME. LOGICAL INDUCTION, AND LEGAL REASONING, 2019
Alternative Perspectives on Induction, 2014