Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
We give an extension of de Finetti's concept of coherence to unbounded (but real-valued) random variables that allows for gambling in the presence of infinite previsions. We present a finitely additive extension of the Daniell integral to unbounded random variables that we believe has advantages over Lebesgue-style integrals in the finitely additive setting. We also give a general version of the Fundamental Theorem of Prevision to deal with conditional previsions and unbounded random variables. 1. Introduction. De Finetti (1974) presented a theory of finitely additive probability in which the concept of prevision played the roles of both probability and expected value (or expectation). De Finetti's theory was motivated in two different, but equivalent, manners. First, he developed a theory of coherent gambling in which a bookie chooses fair prices for gambles while trying to avoid uniform sure loss. Second, he took a decision-theoretic approach in which an agent chooses previsions for random variables while being subject to a loss function. The agent tries to avoid choosing previsions such that an alternative choice could achieve uniformly smaller loss. De Finetti developed his theory fairly completely for the case in which all random variables under consideration are bounded. He realized that unbounded random variables introduce interesting issues for his theory, but he did not pursue those issues very far. Crisma, Gigante, and Millossovich (1997) and Crisma and Gigante (2001) present one form of an extension of de Finetti's theory to unbounded random variables. This paper presents a number of extensions that are more in the spirit of de Finetti's original theory. Section 2 gives a brief summary of de Finetti's theory for random variables with finite previsions and the notation that will be used in the rest of the paper. Section 3 gives our extension of coherence to infinite previsions and compares the extension to the existing extension of Crisma et al. (1997) and Crisma and Gigante (2001). Section 4 shows how the fair price and decision theoretic motivations of de Finetti's theory remain equivalent in the extension to unbounded random variables and to more general loss functions than de Finetti originally envisioned. Section 5 gives an introduction to finitely additive Daniell integrals along with their relation to finitely additive expectations and MSC 2000 subject classifications. Primary 62A01; secondary 62C05.
2018
We extend de Finetti's (1974) theory of coherence to apply also to unbounded random variables. We show that for random variables with mandated infinite prevision, such as for the St. Petersburg gamble, coherence precludes indifference between equivalent random quantities. That is, we demonstrate when the prevision of the difference between two such equivalent random variables must be positive. This result conflicts with the usual approach to theories of Subjective Expected Utility, where preference is defined over lotteries. In addition, we explore similar results for unbounded variables when their previsions, though finite, exceed their expected values, as is permitted within de Finetti's theory. In such cases, the decision maker's coherent preferences over random quantities is not even a function of probability and utility. One upshot of these findings is to explain further the differences between Savage's theory (1954), which requires bounded utility for non-simpl...
brunodefinetti.it
In the fundamental books on "Teoria delle Probabilitµa" [1], by Bruno de Finetti, two different approaches to the conditional probability and prevision are con-sidered. One of these starts from the axiomatic of the finitely additive conditional probability. It is based on the ...
2010
In the insurance literature it is often argued that private markets can provide insurance against 'risk' but not against 'uncertainties' in the sense of Knight (1921) or Keynes (1921). This claim is at odds with the standard economic model of risk exchange which, in assuming that decision-makers are always guided by precise point-valued subjective probabilities, predicts that all uncertainties can, in theory, be insured. Supporters of the standard model argue that the insuring of highly idiosyncratic risks by Lloyd's of London proves that this is so even in practice. The purpose of this paper is to show that Bruno de Finetti, widely regarded as one of the three founding fathers of the subjective approach to probability assumed by the standard model, actually made a theoretical case for uncertainty within the subjectivist approach. We draw on empirical evidence from the practice of underwriters to show how this case may help explain the reluctance of insurers to cover highly uncertain contingencies.
2013
De Finetti's betting argument is used to justify finitely additive probabilities when only finitely many bets are considered. Under what circumstances can countably many bets be used to justify countable additivity? In this framework, one faces issues such as the convergence of the returns of the bet. Generalizations of de Finetti's [4] argument depend on what type of conditions on convergence are required of the bets under consideration. Two new such conditions are compared with others presented in the literature.
The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 2012
In the insurance literature it is often argued that private markets can provide insurance against 'risks' but not against 'uncertainties' in the sense of Knight ([1921]) or Keynes ([1921]). This claim is at odds with the standard economic model of risk exchange which, in assuming that decision-makers are always guided by precise point-valued subjective probabilities, predicts that all uncertainties can, in theory, be insured. Supporters of the standard model argue that the insuring of highly idiosyncratic risks by Lloyd's of London proves that this is so even in practice. The purpose of this paper is to show that Bruno de Finetti, famous as one of the three founding fathers of the subjective approach to probability assumed by the standard model, actually made a theoretical case for uncertainty within the subjectivist approach. We draw on empirical evidence from the practice of underwriters to show how this case may help explain the reluctance of insurers to cover highly uncertain contingencies. 2 Knight and Keynes on the philosophy of unknown probabilities and Lloyd's of London 2.1 Knight 2.2 Keynes 3 Insuring unique events: the subjectivist viewpoint as represented by de Finetti 4 The 'philosophy' of practitioners 5 De Finetti on uncertainty in Knight and Keynes and on insurability 5.1 De Finetti on Knight
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 2014
The well-known Knightian distinction between quantifiable risk and unquantifiable uncertainty is at odds with the dominant subjectivist conception of probability associated with de Finetti, Ramsey and Savage. Risk and uncertainty are rendered indistinguishable on the subjectivist approach insofar as an individual's subjective estimate of the probability of any event can be elicited from the odds at which she would be prepared to bet for or against that event. The risk/uncertainty distinction has however never quite gone away and is currently under renewed theoretical scrutiny. The purpose of this article is to show that de Finetti's understanding of the distinction is more nuanced than is usually admitted. Relying on usually overlooked excerpts of de Finetti's works commenting on Keynes, Knight and interval valued probabilities, we argue that de Finetti suggested a relevant theoretical case for uncertainty to hold even when individuals are endowed with subjective probabilities. Indeed, de Finetti admitted that the distinction between risk and uncertainty is relevant when different individuals sensibly disagree about the probability of the occurrence of an event. We conclude that the received interpretation of de Finetti's understanding of subjective probability needs to be qualified on this front.
… Probabilities and their Applications. Ithaca, NY, 2001
In this paper coherent risk measures and other currently used risk measures, notably Value-at-Risk (VaR), are studied from the perspective of the theory of coherent imprecise previsions. We introduce the notion of coherent risk measure defined on an arbitrary set of risks, showing that it can be considered a special case of coherent upper prevision. We also prove that our definition generalizes the notion of coherence for risk measures defined on a linear space of random numbers, given in literature. We also show that Value-at-Risk does not necessarily satisfy a weaker notion of coherence called ‘avoiding sure loss’ (ASL), and discuss both sufficient conditions for VaR to avoid sure loss and ways of modifying VaR into a coherent risk measure.
De Finetti introduced the concept of coherent previsions and conditional previsions through a gambling argument and through a parallel argument based on a quadratic scoring rule. He shows that the two arguments lead to the same concept of coherence. When dealing with events only, there is a rich class of scoring rules which might be used in place of the quadratic scoring rule. We give conditions under which a general strictly proper scoring rule can replace the quadratic scoring rule while preserving the equivalence of de Finetti's two arguments. In proving our results, we present a strengthening of the usual minimax theorem. We also present generalizations of de Finetti's fundamental theorem of prevision to deal with conditional previsions. (de Finetti, 1974, vol. 1) provides two criteria of coherence for previsions (or probabilistic forecasts) over a set of bounded random variables. The first criterion is formulated under the assumption that previsions serve as fair prices for buying and/or selling contracts of the form c(X − P (X)). Here, P (X) is the prevision of the bounded random variable X, and X is defined on the set Ω whose generic element is denoted ω. With c positive, the decision maker will pay the price cP (X) and receive cX(ω) units in state ω. With c negative, the decision maker sells this gamble on X and receives a payment of cP (X) units. With c = 0, the decision maker remains at his status-quo fortune. Furthermore, conditional previsions are also defined as fair prices for buying and/or selling contracts of the form cI B [X − P (X|B)]. Here, B is an event and I B is its indicator. The contract has 0 value if B does not occur. It is easy to see that, if B = Ω, P (X|B) has the same operational meaning as P (X). In this way, previsions are special cases of conditional previsions. We refer to conditional previsions for which B = Ω as marginal previsions when the need arises. When we refer to previsions unqualified, we mean both marginal and conditional previsions.
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2013
The investigation reported in this paper aims at clarifying an important yet subtle distinction between (i) the logical objects on which measure theoretic probability can be defined, and (ii) the interpretation of the resulting values as rational degrees of belief. Our central result can be stated informally as follows. Whilst all subjective degrees of belief can be expressed in terms of a probability measure, the converse doesn't hold: probability measures can be defined over linguistic objects which do not admit of a meaningful betting interpretation. The logical framework capable of expressing this will allow us to put forward a precise formalisation of de Finetti's notion of event which lies at the heart of the Bayesian approach to uncertain reasoning. 1 Introduction: the epistemic structure of de Finetti's betting interpretation De Finetti's theory of subjective probability is well-known and widely scrutinized in the literature (cf. [2]), so we will review only on those aspects which are directly relevant to our present purposes 1. Let θ 1 ,. .. , θ n be events of interest. De Finetti's betting problem is the choice that an idealised agent called bookmaker must make when publishing a book, i.e. when making an assignment B = {(θ i , β i) : i = 1,. .. , n} in which each event of interest θ i is given value β i ∈ [0, 1]. Once a book has been published, a gambler can place bets S i ∈ R on any event θ i by paying S i β i to the bookmaker. In return for this payment, the gambler will receive S i , if θ i obtains and nothing otherwise. Note that "betting on θ i " effectively amounts, for the gambler, to choosing a real-valued S i which determines the amount payable to the bookmaker 2 .
2011
An account of the first encounter, in 1938, of de Finetti with the notion of martingale is given. The reasons, of an actuarial nature, which led him to deal with the subject are explained, along with a description of the ensuing original contributions to the specific field of martingales. The value of some of his conclusions is, then, discussed in the light of later development of the theory. The note is completed by a few remarks about an interpretative problem concerning the connection between the risk aversion criterion and the (actuarial) criterion based on the riskiness level.
Social Science Research Network, 2000
Statistical Methods and Applications, 2014
Let L be a linear space of real random variables on the measurable space (Ω, A). Conditions for the existence of a probability P on A such that E P |X| < ∞ and E P (X) = 0 for all X ∈ L are provided. Such a P may be finitely additive or σ-additive, depending on the problem at hand, and may also be requested to satisfy P ∼ P 0 or P P 0 where P 0 is a reference measure. As a motivation, we note that a plenty of significant issues reduce to the existence of a probability P as above. Among them, we mention de Finetti's coherence principle, equivalent martingale measures, equivalent measures with given marginals, stationary and reversible Markov chains, and compatibility of conditional distributions.
International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 2015
Betting methods, of which de Finetti's Dutch Book is by far the most well-known, are uncertainty modelling devices which accomplish a twofold aim. Whilst providing an (operational) interpretation of the relevant measure of uncertainty, they also provide a formal definition of coherence. The main purpose of this paper is to put forward a betting method for belief functions on MV-algebras of many-valued events which allows us to isolate the corresponding coherence criterion, which we term coherence in the aggregate. Our framework generalises the classical Dutch Book method.
2021
In utility theory, certain infinite gambles pose problems, of which the St. Petersberg paradox is the most well-known. Various methods have been used to eliminate the paradoxes, including the supposition that utility is bounded, or that probabilities must decline faster than utility so as to always result in finite expectation values, or simply excluding the divergent gambles by definition. We present a unified resolution of the matter that allows for unbounded utility and accommodates convergent infinite gambles. We also argue that merely excluding the divergent gambles, by whatever method, does not entirely avoid the associated paradoxes, which in practical terms already show up for finite approximations to them.
Journal of Mathematical Economics, 2009
When real-valued utilities for outcomes are bounded, or when all variables are simple, it is consistent with expected utility to have preferences defined over probability distributions or lotteries. That is, under such circumstances two variables with a common probability distribution over outcomes -equivalent variables -occupy the same place in a preference ordering. However, if strict preference respects uniform, strict dominance in outcomes between variables, and if indifference between two variables entails indifference between their difference and the status quo, then preferences over rich sets of unbounded variables, such as variables used in the St. Petersburg paradox, cannot preserve indifference between all pairs of equivalent variables. In such circumstances, preference is not a function only of probability and utility for outcomes. Then the preference ordering is not defined in terms of lotteries. Let T be independent of Y and let it have the uniform distribution on the interval [0,1]. Partition the interval [0,1] into the subintervals I 0 =[0, ], and I 1 ,…, I 2 m 1, where the last 2 m 1 intervals are all of equal length, 2 -m . Define the events B i ={T I i } for i=0,1,…,2 m 1 .
We prove the existence of an expected utility function for preferences over probabilistic prospects satisfying Strict Monotonicity, Indifference, the Common Ration Property, Substitution and Reducibility of Extreme Prospects. The example in Rubinstein (1988) that is inconsistent with the existence of a von Neumann-Morgenstern for preferences over probabilistic prospects, violates the Common Ratio Property. Subsequently, we prove the existence of expected utility functions with piecewise linear Bernoulli utility functions for preferences that are piece-wise linear. For this case a weaker version of the Indifference Assumption that is used in the earlier existence theorems is sufficient. We also state analogous results for probabilistic lotteries. We do not require any compound prospects or mixture spaces to prove any of our results. In the second last section of this paper, we “argue” that the observations related to Allais paradox, do not constitute a violation of expected utility maximization by individuals, but is a likely manifestation of individuals assigning (experiment or menu-dependent?) subjective probabilities to events which disagree with their objective probabilities.
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2013
We consider conditional random quantities (c.r.q.'s) in the setting of coherence. Given a numerical r.q. X and a non impossible event H, based on betting scheme we represent the c.r.q. X|H as the unconditional r.q. XH + µH c , where µ is the prevision assessed for X|H. We develop some elements for an algebra of c.r.q.'s, by giving a condition under which two c.r.q.'s X|H and Y |K coincide. We show that X|HK coincides with a suitable c.r.q. Y |K and we apply this representation to Bayesian updating of probabilities, by also deepening some aspects of Bayes' formula. Then, we introduce a notion of iterated c.r.q. (X|H)|K, by analyzing its relationship with X|HK. Our notion of iterated conditional cannot formalize Bayesian updating but has an economic rationale. Finally, we define the coherence for prevision assessments on iterated c.r.q.'s and we give an illustrative example.
Statistical Methods & Applications, 2014
Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 1988
This paper presents an axiomatization of subjective risk judgments that leads to a representation of risk in terms of seven free parameters. This is shown to have considerable predictive ability for risk judgments made by 10 subjects. The risk function retains many of the features of the expectation modeIs--e.g., a constant number of parameters independent of the number of outcomes-but it also allows for asymmetric effects of transformations on positive and negative outcomes. This arises by axiomatizing independently the behavior with respect to gambles having entirely positive outcomes and those with entirely negative outcomes. Complex gambles are decomposed into these, and zero outcomes, using the expected risk property. The resulting risk function compares favorable with other functions previously suggested. It is also demonstrated that preference judgments are distinct from risk judgments, and that the theory does not apply as well to the former.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.