Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2018, Ecdysis
AI
The essay explores the paradoxical relationship between suffering, life, and personal mastery through a mythological narrative featuring characters such as Mortem and Impeditus. It posits that true strength and human progress come from the ability to endure and embrace pain and chaos, suggesting that overcoming adversity is essential for personal growth and helping others. The conclusion reinforces the idea that by accepting and navigating through the worst facets of life, individuals can unlock their fullest potential and appreciate the beautiful complexity of existence.
Candide and Rasselas: of being mortal and in search for happiness Throughout the history of human intellect, philosophy has ventured to contribute to the improvement of the individual, to guess upon the mysteries of the mortal life and question the existence of the immortal one. In the eighteenth century, in particular, we detect a shift towards a more anthropocentric philosophy that aimed in presenting the human existence in the context of a social and natural environment, stressing the questionable capability of the individual to find his own happiness in a world that is anything but stable. In order to understand this shift we have to be aware of the historical context of the era; in this particular period, when the world was continually threatened by war and oppression, the need to define how happiness can be attained in this exact environment was a crucial challenge. The personal awareness of the individual and its contribution to a better social/ personal life was raised. Candide and Rasselas represent this exact realization by setting it as the primary core of their philosophic context. Although in Candide the tragicomic substance of life is prominent while in Rasselas we detect a more introvert speculation on the limits of mortality, the two literary works share the same inevitable inquiry: is it possible for anyone to acquire happiness when he is limited by his mortal nature?
Murphy, Russell, and Stoeger, 2007
2017
In a brief chapter of The Theory of Moral Sentiments entitled "Of the Passions that Take their Origin from the Body," Adam Smith remarks on Sophocles' often-criticized play, Philoctetes, in order to make a point that will resonate, like the cries of suffering Philoctetes, throughout his moral philosophical text as a whole: "In some of the Greek tragedies," such as Euripides' Hippolytus and Sophocles' Trahiniae, but especially Philoctetes, "there is an attempt to excite compassion, by the representation of the agonies of bodily pain. Philoctetes cries out and faints from the extremity of his suffering." 1 According to Smith, however, it is not Philoctetes' infamous snakebite wound that incites the spectator's compassion, nor his inhuman cries and excruciating suffering that make this a compelling drama. On the contrary, Philoctetes' injured foot-"Or," as Seamus Heaney's The Cure at Troy describes it, "what had been a foot before it rotted/And ate itself with ulcers"as well as his uncontrollable outbursts and imprecations threaten to make Sophocles' play, according to Smith, "perfectly ridiculous." 2 If Philoctetes relied merely on presenting the hero's physical suffering and inarticulate cries, it would be "regarded as among the greatest breaches of decorum of which the Greek theatre has set the example." 3 But for Smith, Philoctetes can be salvaged at the expense of the wounded foot and the play's fascination with physical suffering more generally. "It is not the sore foot, but the solitude, of Philoctetes which affects us, and diffuses over that charming tragedy, that romantic wildness, which is so agreeable to the imagination." 4 The lesson to be
In this article, I consider Aristotle’s discussion of the contemplative life as a response to the fundamentally destabilizing menace of misfortune and an uncertain future. Beginning with a recapitulation of how that menace emerges in NE I.10, I then investigate how several passages in NE X.6-9 can be read as responding to it. The perfect completeness of contemplative activity is contrasted with the necessary incompleteness of purposive, practical activities that always aim at something beyond themselves, even when they also happen to be ends in themselves (e.g., political virtues such as courage and justice). I closely analyze how the happiness of the contemplative life is supposed to be more durable and continuous than other human activities, including practical activity within a political context. Drawing on Aristotle’s account of intellect in De Anima III, I argue that since the characteristic activity of intellect (νοῦς), intellection, is invulnerable to harm in its engagement with its objects, this confers a kind of divine blessedness on the contemplative life. Yet even a life characterized by contemplation, to the extent that the human being is a rational animal, remains exposed to misfortune to an unsettling degree. This tension between the human being’s highest actualization as intellective activity, a perfection that seems to finally unite human being and divinity in the carrying out of a divine and blessed human life, and the human being’s animal, mortal nature, embodied, exposed to harmful influences in its environment, subject to suffering, is treated in the light of Homer’s story of Odysseus’ stay on Calypso’s island (Od. V) to argue that ultimately such a blessed life requires too high of a price and that we should, like Odysseus, reject the possibility to become divine if that means losing everything that makes human life precious and irreplaceable.
The Philosophy of Suffering, 2019
On the face of it, suffering from the loss of a loved one and suffering from intense pain are very different things. What makes them both experiences of suffering? I argue it’s neither their unpleasantness nor the fact that we desire not to have such experiences. Rather, what we suffer from negatively transforms the way our situation as a whole appears to us. To cash this out, I introduce the notion of negative affective construal, which involves practically perceiving our situation as calling for change, registering this perception with a felt desire for change, and believing that the change is not within our power. We (attitudinally) suffer when negative affective construal is pervasive, either because it colours a large swath of possibilities, as in the case of anxiety, or because it narrows our attention to what hurts, as in the case of grief. On this view, sensory or bodily suffering is a special case of attitudinal suffering: the unpleasantness of pain causes pervasive negative affective construal. Pain that doesn’t negatively transform our world doesn’t make for suffering.
The Philosophical Forum, 2011
Analysis, 2019
Some people claim that some instances of suffering are intrinsically bad in an impersonal way. If it were true, that claim might seem to count against virtue ethics and for consequentialism. Drawing on the works of Jason Kawall, Christine Swanton and Nietzsche, I consider some reasons for thinking that it is, however, false. I argue, moreover, that even if it were true, a virtue ethicist could consistently acknowledge its truth.
2016
REFLECTIONS ON EVIL ' O Nikos Psarros (Νίκος ΐ'αρρός) είναι καθηγητής φιλοσοφίας στο Ινστιτούτο Φιλοσοφίας του Πανεπιστημίου της Λειψίας.
ANQ: A Quarterly Journal of Short Articles, Notes and Reviews
Genealogy, 2021
The utopian notion that there is a time and place where perfect happiness exists is deeply rooted in Western thought and alienates people from life in the here and now. Happiness is perceived as the purpose of life. Moreover, happiness and suffering are presented as opposites that are contingent upon a person’s actions. For thousands of years, happiness and the avoidance of suffering have been presented as the motives behind every action, and the conceptual basis for this still exists in contemporary discourse and culture. The roots of this perception can be found, inter alia, in the culture’s religious texts. In this paper, we use the genealogical method to interrogate the religious and constitutive texts of Western culture and to examine the origins of the perception that happiness is the purpose of life and that it constitutes the opposite of suffering. The genealogical method enables us to deconstruct the causal relationship that lies at the core of this premise. Genealogy deals...
CLEaR, 2016
To handle physical, mental or existential pain, man resorts to medicine, psychology, religion, philosophy ... This issue has also been discussed by writers and painters of all epochs. Artists have the advantage though - using the language of art, they can reach the truth about human life which cannot be accessed in a different way.The departure point for the deliberations about suffering and the sense of debating about it by means of words and pictures is a poem by W. H. Auden “Musée des Beaux-Arts”, from which the title quotation is derived. Auden refers to P. Bruegel’s Landscape with the Fall of Icarus, which applies to Ovid. In this paper, besides the aforementioned works (Auden, Bruegel; Metamorphoses), other paintings by Bruegel as well as the prose by Z. Herbert The Passion of our Lord Painted by an Anonymous Hand from the Circle of Rhenish Masters are used, allowing one to reflect on suffering, on the language of art, on making sense of the work in the reception process, and ...
Review of Education, Pedagogy, and Cultural Studies, 2023
This article argues that hope is not an adequate affective response to dread. Indeed, hope and dread are more closely aligned than either critical or postcritical forms of educational philosophy would like to admit. The article proposes a shift from hope to joy as an under appreciated educational affect. To make this claim, the author pivots to Spinoza's emphasis on joy as an affect that increases one's potential to think and act in a world with others as a new starting point for education in dreadful times. The article also offers a Spinozian reading of Freire that unlocks the joyful dimensions of his work, especially through his reflections on laughter. In conclusion, a hopelessly joyful affective orientation is called for as a form of passionate educational experimentation with the potentiality of the world.
Philosophers have long argued over the nature of free-will; whether one is forced to enact a predetermined cosmic or biological mandate or whether one is free to truly determine their own destiny. Yet, regardless of the true state of external affairs, one can effectively live their life as if either proposition is correct. To internalize the notion of radical free will can be called existentialism, whereas the internalization of predeterminism labels one a fatalist. While it may be impossible to answer the ontological question of external free will, it is certainly possible to examine those lives who commit themselves to either form. Aside from the naturalists like Stephen Crane who trap their many Maggies in the bondage of biological happenstance, most modern fiction allows its characters the freedom to adopt an internalized stance on free will. The notion of existential responsibility weighs heavily in the pages of Julian Barnes’ novel The Sense of an Ending, with direct mention of Camus’ The Myth of Sisyphus included in the immortalized quote “suicide [is] the only true philosophical question” (Barnes 15). The previously stated separation between fatalism and existentialism is not cast as a dichotomy within this paper, but as a continuum upon which the individual fluctuates. When one loses a clear sense of their personal freedom he naturally gravitates towards fatalism, for the world then begins to act upon him instead of him upon it. Likewise, one necessarily overcomes fatalism to reach a state of personal responsibility, rejecting the world’s existential pressure and internalizing a distinct purpose. Barnes’ protagonist, the “average” Tony who only wants “life not to bother” him, rides the rail between a man condemned to fate and one who moves with internal purpose. Defying the natural progression assumed in the novel format, he peaks at the middle and declines into despair, discontent that his weak attempts at redemption and purpose fall short. He represents a realistic existential portrayal, one detached from the pristine perfection that an Absurd hero like Sisyphus embodies. While Camus asserts that “one must imagine Sisyphus happy,” that the eternal struggle against meaninglessness is enough in itself to fuel a man’s continued existence, Tony demonstrates that this is only truly applicable in theory (Camus 78). The mythic Sisyphus can accept radical responsibility for his actions and live in joyful rebellion, but Tony cannot help but succumb to guilt, crippling remorse, and the shackles of external responsibility, beaten down by his failed reconciliation and inability to, until the end of the novel, make sense of the events surrounding him.
Camus’ Meursault and Sophocles’ Antigone are both characters in literature who act in ways that require them to deliberately confront their own mortality. In both cases, their actions lead to their executions, requiring that they struggle with the meaning and fear of death. ese two cases raise issues of hope, acceptance of the truth of the human condition, and the question of what di erence human action can make given the inevitability of death. I propose to examine both examples as a way of working through two possible stories of death. To set a frame, I begin with Hannah Arendt’s description of the fundamental levels of human activity and the di erent relation each activity has to death.
The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 1981
This chapter explores classical Mediterranean thought on suffering through a detailed examination of one Greek tragedy, Sophocles' Philoctetes, in which both moral philosophy and medicine also feature. Suffering in this play has no inherent metaphysical or ethical status, but it does raise the rather practical as well as ethical question of how other human beings can and should respond to the sufferer-examining in close detail how an individual's acute suffering deforms his everyday life and his relationships with his or her community and showing how very differently individuals respond to the suffering of others. It even asks the proto-Utilitarian question of whether the suffering of a single individual should be allowed to outweigh the interests of the whole community. There is perhaps no other artwork that explores so intensely the problem which incurable suffering presents to the community to which the sufferer belongs.
South African journal of philosophy, 2009
Epicurus argued that death can be neither good nor bad because it involves neither pleasure nor pain. This paper focuses on the deprivation account as a response to this Hedonist Argument. Proponents of the deprivation account hold that Epicurus's argument fails even if death involves no painful or pleasurable experiences and even if the hedonist ethical system, which holds that pleasure and pain are all that matter ethically, is accepted. I discuss four objections that have been raised against the deprivation account and argue that this response to Epicurus's argument is successful once it has been sufficiently clarified.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.