Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
17 pages
1 file
There is almost a consensus among conditional experts that indicative conditionals are not material. Their thought hinges on the idea that if indicative conditionals were material, A → B could be vacuously true when A is false, even if B would be false in a context where A is true. But since this consequence is implausible, the material account is usually regarded as false. It is argued that this point of view is motivated by the grammatical form of conditional sentences and the symbols used to represent their logical form, which misleadingly suggest a one-way inferential direction from A to B. That conditional sentences mislead us into a directionality bias is a phenomenon that is well-documented in the literature about conditional reasoning. It is argued that this directional appearance is deceptive and does not reflect the underlying truth conditions of conditional sentences. This directional bias is responsible for both the unpopularity of the material account of conditionals and some of the main alternative principles and themes in conditional theory, including the Ramsey’s test, the Equation, Adams’ thesis, conditional-assertion and possible world theories. The directional mindset forgets a hard- earned lesson that made classical logic possible in the first place, namely, that grammatical form of sentences can mislead us about its truth conditions. There is a case to be made for a material account of indicative conditionals when we break the domination of words over the human mind.
There is a profound, but frequently ignored relationship between logical consequence (formal implication) and material implication. The first repeats the patterns of the latter, but with a wider modal reach. It is argued that this kinship between formal and material implication simply means that they express the same kind of implication, but differ in scope. Formal implication is unrestricted material implication. This apparently innocuous observation has some significant corollaries: (1) conditionals are not connectives, but arguments; (2) the traditional examples of valid argumentative forms are metalogical principles that express the properties of logical consequence; (3) formal logic is not a useful guide to detect valid arguments in the real world; (4) it is incoherent to propose alternatives to the material implication while accepting the classical properties of formal implication; (5) some of the counter-examples to classical argumentative forms and known conditional puzzles are unsound.
The material account of indicative conditionals faces a legion of counterexamples that are the bread and butter in any entry about the subject. For this reason, the material account is widely unpopular among conditional experts. I will argue that this consensus was not built on solid foundations, since these counterexamples are contextual fallacies. They ignore a basic tenet of semantics according to which when evaluating arguments for validity we need to maintain the context constant, otherwise any argumentative form can be rendered invalid. If we maintain the context fixed, the counterexamples to the material account are disarmed. Throughout the paper I also consider the ramifications of this defence, make suggestions to prevent contextual fallacies, and anticipate some possible misunderstandings and objections.
This is the first part of two in a study on the logic and semantics of the indicative conditional. This first part provides a global expressivist analysis of the indicative conditional along the lines of the Ramsey Test. The analysis is a form of 'global' expressivism in that it supplies acceptance and rejection conditions for all the sentence forming connectives of propositional logic (negation, disjunction, etc.) and so allows the conditional to embed in arbitrarily complex sentences (thus avoiding the Frege-Geach problem). The resulting mental usage semantics is provably not susceptible to triviality results and completely characterises a logic for the indicative conditional that respects many of its well known logical quirks (the failure of modus ponens, etc.). The second part provides a semantic analysis of the resulting structure and logic.
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2015
The Spanish Journal of Psychology, 2015
Directionality effect in deductive reasoning is a very well-known phenomenon that shows that the percentage of forward or backward inferences that participants make depends on the conditional form used. A new extension of the semantic hypothesis (Oberauer & Wilhelm, 2000) is presented to explain the directionality effect in double conditionals with different directionality. This hypothesis claims that the directional effect depends on which term plays the role of relatum. It also makes several novel claims which have been confirmed in three experiments: Experiments 1 and 2 showed there were more forward than backward inferences when the end-term that played the role of relatum was in the first premise, experiment 1:t(45) = 2.73,p< .01, experiment 2:t(38) = 12.06,p< .05, but there were more backward than forward inferences when the end-term that played the role of relatum was in the second premise, experiment 1: t(45) = 2.84,p< .01, experiment 2:t(38) = 2.21,p< .04. Exper...
Studia Logica, 2008
I argue that indicative conditionals are best viewed as having truth conditions (and so they are in part factual) but that these truth conditions are `gappy' which leaves an explanatory gap that can only be ¯lled by epistemic considerations (and so indicative conditionals are in part epistemic). I argue that this dual nature of indicative conditionals forces us to rethink the relationship between logic viewed as a descriptive discipline (focusing on semantics) and logic viewed as a discipline with a normative import (focusing on epistemic notions such as `reasoning', `beliefs' and `assumptions'). In particular, I argue that the development of formal models for epistemic states can serve as a starting point for exploring logic when viewed as a normative discipline.
Topoi, 2009
This paper replies to criticisms of the mental model theory of conditionals. It argues that the theory provides a correct account of negation of conditionals, that it does not provide a truth-functional account of their meaning, though it predicts that certain interpretations of conditionals yield acceptable versions of the 'paradoxes' of material implication, and that it postulates three main strategies for estimating the probabilities of conditionals.
The goal of this paper is to test the main predictions of the semantic hypothesis about the directional effect in double conditionals (such as, 'A only if B/only if C, B') with a construction task. The semantic hypothesis claims that directional effect can be explained by the inherent directionality of the relation between the relatum and the target object of the premises. According to this hypothesis, a directional effect should occur if only one of the end-terms of the premises takes the role of relatum: a) if the end-term that plays the role of relatum is in the first premise, a forward directional effect is predicted (from A to C); and b) if the end-term that plays the role of relatum is in the second premise, a backward directional effect is predicted (from C to A). On the other hand, it claims that there should be no directional effect when both end-terms take the role of relatum or when neither of the end-terms plays the role of relatum. Three experiments confirmed the main predictions of the semantic hypothesis in a construction task.
Adam Rieger (2013) has carried out a survey of arguments in favour of the material account of indicative conditionals. These arguments involve simple and direct demonstrations of the material account. I extend the survey with new arguments and clarify the logical connections among them. I also show that the main counterexamples against these arguments are not successful either because their premises are just as counter-intuitive as the conclusions, or because they depend on contextual fallacies. The conclusion is that the unpopularity of the material account is unjustified and that a more systematic approach in the analysis of arguments is long overdue in our attempts to understand the nature of conditionals.
This simple defense of material implication helps clarify the debate between the orthodox logicians, who claim 'If p then q' and 'p |horseshoe| q' are not interderivable and the nonorthodox logicians, who claim that the two expressions are interderivable. The paper shows the orthodox logician must deny that ordinary language arguments of the form modus ponens and modus tollens are truth-functional in any consistent sense on three lines of the truth-table.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 1981
Philosophical Studies, 2021
Logical Investigations, 2021
The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 2010
Synthese, 2012
Psychological Review, 2002
Dissertation, Faculty of Economics and Behavioral Sciences, University of Freiburg, 2017
Memory & Cognition, 1994
Thinking & Reasoning, 2019
European Review of Philosophy, The Nature of Logic ( …, 1999
Review of Symbolic Logic, 2020
Experimental Psychology (formerly "Zeitschrift für Experimentelle Psychologie"), 2008