Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2009, Configurations
AI
This paper explores the relationship between mathematics and imagination, questioning the nature of mathematical objects and concepts. It examines historical philosophical perspectives, contrasting views on the existence of mathematics, and highlights how imagination plays a crucial role in mathematical thought and understanding.
Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity
Chapter 8 considers the role of the imagination as it appears in Proclus’ commentary on Euclid, where mathematical or geometrical objects are taken to mediate, both ontologically and cognitively, between thinkable and physical things. With the former, mathematical things share the permanence and consistency of their properties; with the latter, they share divisibility and the possibility of being multiplied. Hence, a geometrical figure exists simultaneously on four different levels: as a noetic concept in the intellect; as a logical definition, or logos, in discursive reasoning; as an imaginary perfect figure in the imagination; and as a physical imitation or representation in sense-perception. Imagination, then, can be equated with the intelligible or geometrical matter that constitutes the medium in which a geometrical object can be constructed, represented, and studied.
2000
A metaphor is an alteration of a woorde from the proper and naturall meanynge, to that which is not proper, and yet agreeth thereunto, by some lykenes that appeareth to be in it. ... —Thomas Wilson, The Arte of Rhetorique ...
COSMIC SPIRIT, 2020
Only the linguistic expression of genuine mathematics is typical, since, as being a language, it is a human construction of symbolic/point patterns which express the earthly dimensional (Euclidean) space-time environment. These extreme spot symbols of mathematical expression are nothing else but the extreme sections of the net (intangible) mathematical universe. Namely, they are material thickenings that take place due to the function of the human brain (1). An example may analyze the above: as electromagnetism is material (electricity) and “power” (“something else”) altogether, the mathematical universe is language (material) and thought (“something else” – “energy”) together. The language should not be coincided with thought (2). On the other hand, neither the thought should be coincided with the written language. Both the oral and the written language are nothing more than a form of the net structure of thought – logic. Logic in turn, should not be coincided with mathematics (neither as being a mathematical logic), because mathematics are an immaterial – invisible “language” which is expressed as a visible material through mathematical symbols – spots. Ultimately, Mathematics themselves cannot be categorized, as we showed, in rationalism or in empiricism (“sensualism”), or in intuitionism (“intuitive mathematics”) either.
Geometries of Nature, Living Systems and Human Cognition, 2005
At the beginning, Nature set up matters its own way and, later, it constructed human intelligence in such a way that [this intelligence] could understand it" [Galileo Galilei, 1632 (Opere, p. 298)]. "The applicability of our science [mathematics] seems then as a symptom of its rooting, not as a measure of its value. Mathematics, as a tree which freely develops his top, draws its strength by the thousands roots in a ground of intuitions of real representations; it would be disastrous to cut them off, in view of a short-sided utilitarism, or to uproot them from the ground from which they rose" [H. Weyl, 1910]. Summary. Mathematics stems out from our ways of making the world intelligible by its peculiar conceptual stability and unity ; we invented it and used it to single out key regularities of space and language. This is exemplified and summarised below in references to the main foundational approaches to Mathematics, as proposed in the last 150 years. Its unity is also stressed: in this paper, Mathematics is viewed as a "three dimensional manifold" grounded on logic, formalisms and invariants of space; we will appreciate by this both its autonomous generative nature and its effectiveness. But effectiveness is also due to the fact that we reconstruct the world by Mathematics: we organise knowledge of space and language by Mathematics, and give meaning by it to their structuring. But, what is "meaning", for us living and historical beings? What does "mathematical intuition" refer to? We will try to propose an understanding of these crucial aspects of the mathematical praxis, often disregarded as "magic" or as beyond any scientific analysis. Finally, some limits of the remarkable, but reasonable effectiveness of Mathematics will be sketched, in particular in reference to its applications in Biology and in human cognition of space, is topological, while the curvature and the metric is a local property, which may depend on the "cohesive forces of matter", an amazing anticipation of Einstein's relativity 2. As a matter of fact, by the analysis of the geometric structure of space (as ether), Riemann meant to unify action at distance (heath, light ... gravitation). Clearly, Riemann greatly contributed, by his n-dimensional differential geometry, to demolish the absolute and certainty of Euclidean space, just a special case of his general approach. Yet, he tried to re-establish knowledge as related to our understanding of the (physical) world. For him, geometry is not "a priori" by its axioms, but it is its grounded on certain regularities of physical space, to be singled out and which have an objective, physical, meaning (continuity, connectivity and isotropy, for example). In Riemann's approach, we actively structure space, as manifold, by focusing on some key properties, which we evidentiate by "adding hypotheses". Thus the foundational analysis consists, for Riemann, Klein, Clifford, Helmoltz ... in making these regularities explicit and in spelling out the transformations which preserve them. However, this "relativized" neo-kantian attitude turned out to be unsatisfactory for many, since it dangerously involved an analysis of the "genesis of concepts", as apparently originating from our more or less subjective presence in the physical world. In fact, these concepts, as for instance those of differential form, group and curvature are objective because they are invariants that we actively single out of the hysical world; that is, they become concepts as a result of the interaction, at the phenomenal level, between us and the world. How to re-establish then absolute certainty and objectiveness, after the shocking revolution of non-Euclidean geometries, while avoiding this "implication of the subject" into knowledge? First, avoid any reference to space and time, the very reference that had given certainty, for so long, not only to geometry, but also to algebra and analysis. For Descartes and Gauss, say, algebraic equations or the imaginary numbers are "understood" in space: this is so in analytic geometry and in Argand-Gauss interpretation, over the Cartesian plane, of √-1 (of the complex numbers, thus). But, if our relation to space is left aside in order to avoid the uncertainties of the "many geometries" and the shaky sands of human cognition, then language remains, in particular the logical laws of thought that the English school of algebra had already been putting forward, in a minimal language of signs ([Boole,1854]). Language, considered as the locus of the manipulation of (logical) symbols, with no reference to phenomenal space, nor, in general, to forms of experience. Frege best represents this turning point, in the foundation of Mathematics. His search
One reason for the " unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics " is that it is never compared to nature itself, which is ambiguous, but to well-defined idealized versions (models). Math is consistent with nature in unfamiliar situations because it is consistent within itself. PART ONE: the Map and the Territory Nature and mathematics are divided by the same categorical gulf that has long plagued the relationship between the physical and the mental. Just as there is no mind without body, there is no mathematics without mathematicians. Mathematics and physics are alike cognitive activities undertaken by intelligent organisms. The relationship of one to the other—and of each to nature—must be considered in their context as embodied cognition. We moderns understand the universe through mathematical models, which are idealized constructs that correspond only approximately to reality. It is easy enough to mistake the model for the reality—the map for the territory—when one has learned to think of nature as literally consisting of such idealizations. This mistake parallels the naïve realism of ordinary cognition, in which we normally take our perception as a transparent window on the world. One can then even conclude that the universe is literally mathematics. It is perfectly reasonable for physicists to believe in the guidance of mathematics. Yet, if physics is a form of cognition, then it is also reasonable to believe in the guidance of cognitive theory, evolutionary psychology, and theoretical epistemology (the nascent science of possible cognitive systems). Such things are not a part of physics as we know it. The Scientific Revolution redefined natural philosophy as " first-order " science: study of the external world in strictly objectivist terms. Focus on the object excluded focus on the subject. Cognition in general is a form of map-making. So, then, are mathematics and physics. The map, however, is not the territory. At best it represents it selectively, symbolically, and adequately for specific purposes. In the case of ordinary cognition, these purposes are bequeathed by evolutionary history. Math and physics may be driven by other purposes as well, better described perhaps by sociology and anthropology. In any case, the map corresponds only grossly to the territory. There is always simplification and streamlining involved. Science tends to mask the real complexity of the world when it presumes simplicity or prefers tidy systems to messy facts. The complexity and messiness of nature are the signs of its reality, which (contra Plato) lies in its very " imperfection. " We vaunt the ability of mathematics to exhaustively represent natural systems, but the reality of nature lies precisely in its ability to resist such exhaustion. Mathematical laws generally describe ideal things and circumstances that do not occur in nature, and that could not even be stated without idealization, isolation, and experimental control. (Ellis 2002, p90-94) To single out a causal relationship, one must know how the process
THEORIA. An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science
In the first part of the paper, previous work about embodied mathematics and the practice of topology will be presented. According to the proposed view, in order to become experts, topologists have to learn how to use manipulative imagination: representations are cognitive tools whose functioning depends from pre-existing cognitive abilities and from specific training. In the second part of the paper, the notion of imagination as “make-believe” is discussed to give an account of cognitive tools in mathematics as props; to better specify the claim, the notion of “affordance” is explored in its possible extension from concrete objects to representations.
Configurations 17.1-2 (2009), 2009
The monographs and occasional textbooks published in this series tap directly into the kinds of themes, research findings, and general professional activities of the Fields Cognitive Science Network, which brings together mathematicians, philosophers, and cognitive scientists to explore the question of the nature of mathematics and how it is learned from various interdisciplinary angles. The series will cover the following complementary themes and conceptualizations: Connections between mathematical modeling and artificial intelligence research; math cognition and symbolism, annotation, and other semiotic processes; and mathematical discovery and cultural processes, including technological systems that guide the thrust of cognitive and social evolution Mathematics, cognition, and computer science, focusing on the nature of logic and rules in artificial and mental systems The historical context of any topic that involves how mathematical thinking emerged, focusing on archeological and philological evidence Other thematic areas that have implications for the study of math and mind, including ideas from disciplines such as philosophy and linguistics The question of the nature of mathematics is actually an empirical question that can best be investigated with various disciplinary tools, involving diverse types of hypotheses, testing procedures, and derived theoretical interpretations. This series aims to address questions of mathematics as a unique type of human conceptual system versus sharing neural systems with other faculties, whether it is a series-specific trait or exists in some other form in other species, what structures (if any) are shared by mathematics, language, and more. Data and new results related to such questions are being collected and published in various peer-reviewed academic journals. Among other things, data and results have profound implications for the teaching and learning of mathematics. The objective is based on the premise that mathematics, like language, is inherently interpretive and explorative at once. In this sense, the inherent goal is a hermeneutical one, attempting to explore and understand a phenomenon-mathematics-from as many scientific and humanistic angles as possible.
Language and the Creative Mind
Hearing the word "mathematics" often conjures up images of boring high school lectures and arduous problem sets. To many of us, mathematics seems like an overly abstract and seemingly untouchable subject matter, removed from any connection to the real world, and at the same time rigid and unwieldy. The mathematician Zagier (2012: 16) writes that "most people cannot begin to imagine how mathematics and pleasure can be related at all", and he says that some people are even "filled with dread at the mere thought of mathematics" (ibid. 12).
International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, 2018
As mathematics educators, we teach and research a particular form of knowledge. However, in reacting to Platonic views of mathematics, we often overlook its unique characteristics. This paper presents a Kantian and Piagetian perspective that defines mathematics as a product of psychology. This perspective, based in human activity, unites mathematical objects, such as shape and number, while explaining what makes mathematics unique. In so doing, it not only privileges mathematics as a powerful form of knowledge but also empowers students to own its objects as their own constructions. Examples and interdisciplinary research findings (e.g., neuroscience) are provided to elucidate and support the perspective.
If abstract mathematical entities do not really exist, then what really exist in human mathematical practices? For a naturalist and nominalist, they can only be human brain activities in doing and applying mathematics. This paper belongs to a research project exploring a naturalistic and nominalistic account of human mathematical practices by treating them as cognitive activities of human brains. I will introduce some basic assumptions about human cognitive architecture and then discuss several aspects of human mathematical practices on that basis.
Routledge Handbook on the Philosophy of Imagination, 2016
The Mathematical Intelligencer, 2015
Resonance, 2018
In this article, I discuss the relationship of mathematics to the physical world, and to other spheres of human knowledge. In particular, I argue that Mathematics is created by human beings, and the number π can not be said to have existed 100, 000 years ago, using the conventional meaning of the word 'exist'.
Pure mathematics is often seen as an 'inverted pyramid', in which algebra and analysis stand at the focal point, without which students could not possibly have a firm grounding for graduate studies. This paper examines a variety of evidence from brain studies of mathematical cognition, from mathematics in early child development, from studies of the gatherer-hunter mind, from a variety of puzzles, games and other human activities, from theories emerging from physical cosmology, and from burgeoning mathematical resources on the internet that suggest, to the contrary, that mathematics is a cultural language more akin to a maze than a focally-based hierarchy; that topology, geometry and dynamics are fundamental to the human mathematical mind; and that an exclusive focus on algebra and analysis may rather explain an increasing rift between modern mathematics and the 'real world' of the human population.
2008
The role of metaphors and the switch in cognitive modes in relation to visualization in learning and teaching mathematics is discussed, based on examples and case studies with students and teachers. We present some preliminary evidence supporting our claims that visualization requires the activation of various metaphors, that it is rather hampered than facilitated by traditional teaching in mathematics, but it is however a trainable capacity in teachers and students.
2020
Analysing several characteristic mathematical models: natural and real numbers, Euclidean geometry, group theory, and set theory, I argue that a mathematical model in its nal form is a junction of a set of axioms and an internal partial interpretation of the corresponding language. It follows from the analysis that (i) mathematical objects do not exist in the external world: they are our internally imagined objects, some of which, at least approximately, we can realize or represent; (ii) mathematical truths are not truths about the external world but speci cations (formulations) of mathematical conceptions; (iii) mathematics is rst and foremost our imagined tool by which, with certain assumptions about its applicability, we explore nature and synthesize our rational cognition of it. keywords: mathematical models; mathematical objects; mathematical truths; applicability of mathematics The basic problem of the philosophy of mathematics (not mathematics itself) is to answer the followi...
IFOR, 2021
Being a language, mathematics grounds itself into human mind and culture: mathematics reflect the structure of human mind, rather than being an intrinsic property (or domain) of nature. The radical assumption in the theory of symmetrical nature of unconscious, by Matte Blanco (1975), displaces psychology into the domain of physics: that way, the two topics from Freud (1899; 1923) reveal themselves to be seminal tools in order to understand mathematics and its intrinsic unconscious structure, because the various processes of Symmetrization pertain as much to unconscious as to mathematics.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.