Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
39 pages
1 file
Blaise Pascal, Pierre Bourdieu, Michel de Montaigne, John Lyons, Clément Rosset, Michael Oakeshott, habitus and embodiment, situated cognitive subject versus the transcendental subject, embodied ideology, politics of the mind-body-history split, language and ideology as magical thinking, alienation and political embodiment, the Intellectual Stance, pure reason versus embodied practice, cognitive constraints of "pure" thought, cognition and social practice, Pascal's marginalization in academic discourse. Abstract: This paper explores the surprising convergence between Blaise Pascal's philosophical anthropology and Pierre Bourdieu's sociology, which is at heart much more Pascalian than neo-Marxist. A secondary argument here, using Bourdieu's Pascalian description of our core intellectual ethos, also addresses the reasons for the marginalization of Pascal with in the academic study of the French Classical period. Pascal posited an anti-humanism, exemplified in the abyssal discontinuity among the three orders (body, mind, charity), and, above all, by the humiliating limitations he places on human rational agency. Pascal thus collapses the mind/body distinction and replaces it with a far more subtle and dynamic notion of La Machine and L'AUTOMATE, the socialized body of the Common Man as a site of truth in a fallen world. Like Bourdieu late in the twentieth century, Pascal also operates a rehabilitation of the world of appearances, the world of Das Man. Pascal and Bourdieu both attack the MO of the Intellectual Stance: the notion that the intellectual can construct himself or herself as a transcendental subject whose thoughts and discourses hold sway and are transitive with the social and historical world on the basis of pure thought. Bourdieu's analysis of the intellectual overinvestment in the power of reason and the magical power of discourse, the perennial intellectual fantasy of la superbe philosophique, also explains better than any other factor why Pascal's thought is quarantined and largely disregarded in the study of the French 17th Century as well as why it cannot but be this way.
PUBLICATIONES UNIVERSITATIS MISKOLCINENSIS SECTIO PHILOSOPHICA, 2022
In 1918 towards the end of his life, the French poet Guillaume Apollinaire wrote in a letter to Picasso: “What is there today that is newer, more modern, more denuded and more laden with riches than Pascal?” What was it about this seventeenth century physicist, mathematician, inventor, moralist and religious philosopher that elicited such soaring praise from a surrealist poet over 250 years after his death at the young age of thirty-nine? Although Pascal was without a doubt a scientist of formidable genius, it was not his scientific prowess which won him the greatest admiration among the creative minds of the early twentieth century, nor which continues to feed his buoyant reputation at the beginning of the twenty-first. It was rather his profound insights into the workings of the human consciousness, his understanding in an age of humanism emerging from the Renaissance, that humans are, “un milieu entre rien et tout”, a space between nothing and everything, capable of the highest highs and the lowest lows.
University of Toronto Quarterly, 2015
Blaise Pascal has been viewed as a major modern philosopher but today is being increasingly ignored. One of my passions is philosophy and I was shocked to discover that the famous Pascal was totally ignored in the popular “Philosophy: 100 Essential Thinkers” (2010) and “The Story of Philosophy” by Bryan Magee (1998) and “The Oxford Companion to Philosophy” (1995). However, he does merit a four page entry by RH Popkin (Emeritus Philosophy Professor, Washington University-St. Louis, MO) in “Great Thinkers of the Western World” (1992) and a substantial write-up in Wikipedia. Even a Google search on the word Pascal first lists the scientific unit of pressure named in his honour. This essay will examine this major omission of Pascal from the ranks of the principal philosophers of Western Europe. We shall show that he annoyed too many powerful people both then and later, so it was easier to omit him than confront his radical, independent philosophical/religious thinking, while acknowledging his major mathematical achievements and minor scientific research.
Any état présent of Blaise Pascal (1623-62) is bound to start with an acknowledgement of the insuperable editorial difficulties thrown up by the most important text in the Pascalian canon, known, albeit not to him, as the Pensées. The rights and wrongs of how these discontinuous posthumous sections of written material are presented in order to be, as far as possible, both readable and faithful to what we can ascertain of their compilation and purpose have dominated the story of their publication for more than three centuries. The problem might seem to arise uncomplicatedly from the simple fact of Pascal's early death, leaving as it did a vast corpus of preparatory notes for a projected apologia for the Christian religion in a state of disorder and fragmentation. If, then, we begin by turning innocently to their early publication history, we might hope, at least bibliographically, to find some initial points de repère; but these are already fraught with difficulty. The highly selective and theologically tendentious first version of what was to be known to posterity as the Pensées de Monsieur Pascal sur la religion et sur quelques autres sujets (the 'É dition de Port-Royal') was published in 1670, but was marked by the intrusive editorial presence both of his sister Gilberte Périer, and of the Jansenist ethos that characterized the spiritual milieu of Pascal's family and associates. Pascal was linked to the neo-Augustinian theology of the convent of Port-Royal -so much is certain -and clear evidence of that affiliation is present in the editio princeps, which is available as a facsimile in a modern critical presentation. 1 It was also, selfevidently, to this truncated and partisan anthology that writers in the eighteenth century referred when they took issue with or (more rarely) drew inspiration from the arguments which are, or appear to be, the cornerstones of the whole project.
Renaissance Quarterly, 2020
Verbum, 2014
This essay argues that the main instrument Montaigne, 16th-century French thinker and writer, used for creating a "new ontology, " as Nicola Panichi calls it (2004, 278), was language and a special style of writing. He, first of all, created-or revived from the Antiquity-a new genre most suitable for a new discourse, and christened it essai. Then he applied a method known in humanist schools of the Renaissance as ultraquem partem to relativise all previous thought. Finally, he employed a thorough, frank examination of his own behaviour, habits and preferences, adorned with Latin sentences, to promote self-analysis as a path to personal contentment. This article applies the theory of Bakhtin, a 20th-century Russian philosopher and sociolinguist, especially his essay "Discourse in the Novel" ("Слово в романе"), in the analysis of the peculiarity of Montaigne's composition and its purposefulness in expressing at that time dangerous, but already prevalent worldview. Since battling medieval Christian thought was the paramount assignment of his endeavour, the quotes are mostly taken from Montaigne's only essay-and by far the longest in the three-volume collection-entirely dedicated to religion, "Apologie de Raimond Sebond. "
An apt title for a longer essay on Blaise Pascal-the French, seventeenth century scientist, mathematician, philosopher and theologist-developed along a chronological line, could be: from nothing to nothing. The first 'nothing' plays a pivotal role in one of his earliest contributions to the field of physics, and concerns the discussion about the possibility of a vacuum in nature. For more than two thousand years, first by the Aristotelian philosophy of nature, then subsequently supported by Christian theology and philosophy, the existence of nothing, a pure void within the plenitude of being was considered as an impossibility, an odd idea contradicting the widely shared conviction that nature abhors a vacuum. Of course, Pascal was not the first to perform experiments with tubes filled with mercury, water or wine to produce the remarkable creation of seemingly-as we know now thanks to those experiments, also really-empty spaces within those tubes. He may not have been the first to conduct these experiments (Torricelli and Galileo preceded him), reading the reports and discussions of the experiments, reveals Pascal's tenacity. 2 Therein he is not directly arguing in favour or against the philosophically problematic idea of empty space; relying on the impossible idea of a vacuum, he explains the phenomena observed. This eventually allows him to conclude that the lowering of liquids in a tube, turned upside down in a vessel containing the same liquid and producing the vacuum in the upper part of the tube, is entirely due to air pressure. Which is indeed, as Alexandre Koyré once put it, a remarkable way of explaining the real via the impossible 3 , that is via the counter-intuitive idea of a natural nothingness. Taking a leap from the scientific observations and calculations stemming from the early stages of Pascal's adult life, to the months preceding his premature death in 1662 at the 1 Blaise Pascal, Pensées, trans. A.J. Krailsheimer, London: Penguin 1966, 240. This English translation relies on Louis Lafuma's edition of the Pensées. Following a common practice in referring to Pensées, the number of the pensée will be added, according to the Lafuma, Léon Brunschvicg and Philippe Sellier editions, respectively. The motto above is taken from: Laf. 656 / Br. 368 / Sel. 743. 2 See Dominique Descotes, 'Pascal. Le calcul et la théologie', in: Pour la science, 16 (2003), 1-93. 3 Alexandre Koyré, Etudes d'histoire de la pensée scientifique. Paris: Gallimard, 1966, 185-186.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
History of European Ideas, 2020
Scottish Journal of Theology, 1972
European Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Philosophy in Review, 2011
HISTORYKA. Studia Metodologiczne, 2019
Modern Theology, 2011
American Political Thought , 2016
Symplokē, 2015
PliThe Warwick Journal of Philosophy, 1999
CONVIVIUM - REVISTA DE FILOSOFIA, 2020
Cosmos and History - The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, 2021
History of European Ideas, 1995
Philosophy in Review, 2011
The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition, 2012