Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
15 pages
1 file
The main object of this paper is to discuss the philosophical problems that arise once the presuppositions which support Neuroaesthetics, are recognized: The Technology Limitation, The Language of the Machine, The Ambiguity Problem, The Problem of Hermeneutics, The Aesthetic Problem, The Cultural Influence Problem, The Subject Problem, The Problem of Mind/Body Continuity, The Solipsism Problem, and the Problem of Incommensurability of Beauty. A second goal of this paper is to highlight the limitations of studying the aesthetic experience under the constraints of the rigors of science, showing how essential it is to allow the participation of other disciplines like art and philosophy in the Neuroaesthetic field.
The future of the art/science relationship does not only concern the field of artistic creation, but also the field of aesthetic experience. In fact, whereas aesthetics has existed as a philosophical discipline since the 18th century, more and more scientific experimental works study aesthetic experience. Philosophical aesthetics now shares its object of study with what is often called neuroaesthetics. The aim of this chapter is to shape a common vision enabling philosophical aesthetics and neuroaesthetics to pool their results and their tools so that the research world does not suffer from a regrettable scission in the field of theory of artistic theory. Indeed, aesthetics seems to have a lot to gain from physiological studies dealing, on the one hand, with the capacity of cognitive processes to adapt to non-routine situations and, on the other hand, with the capacity of these adaptations to be felt by individuals.
2014
Neuroaesthetics is a young enough field that there seems to be no established view of its proper subject matter. Morphologically, the term implies the scientific study of neural aspects of the perception of artworks such as paintings, or elements of artworks such as musical intervals. We are concerned, however, that practitioners of this new field may not be aware of the tremendous ambiguities inherent in the terms “aesthetics ” and “art, ” ones that limit a proper understanding of human art behavior. Connotations of these terms are particularly inappropriate and mis-leading when considering the experiences, practices, and functions of the arts in preindustrial, folk, aboriginal, or Pleistocene societies, and even in contemporary popular culture. It is only during the last two centuries that the terms “Art ” (with an implied capital A, connoting an independent realm of prestigious and revelatory works) and “aesthetics ” (as a unique, and even reverential, mode of attention toward su...
Neuroaesthetics (M. Skov and O. Vartanian, eds.), 2009
Neuroaesthetics, 2018
Neuroaesthetics is a young enough field that there seems to be no established view of its proper subject matter. Morphologically, the term implies the scientific study of neural aspects of the perception of artworks such as paintings, or elements of artworks such as musical intervals. We are concerned, however, that practitioners of this new field may not be aware of the tremendous ambiguities inherent in the terms "aesthetics" and "art," ones that limit a proper understanding of human art behavior. Connotations of these terms are particularly inappropriate and misleading when considering the experiences, practices, and functions of the arts in preindustrial, folk, aboriginal, or Pleistocene societies, and even in contemporary popular culture. It is only during the last two centuries that the terms "Art" (with an implied capital A, connoting an independent realm of prestigious and revelatory works) and "aesthetics" (as a unique, and even reverential, mode of attention toward such works) have taken on their present elitist meanings and become unavoidably intertwined (Davies, 2006; Shiner, 2001). The word "aesthetic" (from the Greek aiesthesis, having to do with the senses) was first used in 1735 by a German philosopher in a book on poetry (Baumgarten, 1735/1954), and since that time has been employed in two different, but not always distinct, ways. Enlightenment philosophers and their followers gradually developed the now elitist notion of "the aesthetic"-a special form of disinterested knowledge and appreciation-to describe the emotional response elicited by the perception of great works of art (Shiner, 2001). While this meaning of aesthetic has strong historical connections with the arts and with artworks, a second usage has come to refer to any value system having to do with the appreciation of beauty, such as the beauty of nature. In recent decades, for example, some ethologists and evolutionary psychologists have adopted this second, broader notion of aesthetics in a new field, originally called "landscape
2023
Since ancient, if not primordial, times, humans wondered about art: why do we have art? How did we come to have art? What is the value of having art? Why do we experience pleasure in relation to art, and why does some art engender more pleasure than other art, and that only, apparently, for some people and not for all of us? Answering such questions is beyond the scope of a single book. Nor is it appropriate for a course manual to do more than set out the questions, provide informative contexts as well as equip readers and students with a basic set of skills to enable them to at least begin a journey of discovery. Hence, the present textbook aims to offer exactly that. We will begin a marvellous questing journey and walk the sometimes beaten, sometimes arduous, path, together, for a
2015
This article surveys the research and findings of neuroaesthetics, a subfield of neurology and empirical aesthetics. The main motivation for this line of research, which dates back to 2002 and probably even earlier, is a scientific study of the visual information processed by a human brain that is connected to or influenced by an aesthetic judgment. We discuss here mainly the work of S. Zeki, considered by many the founder of neuroaesthetics. We argue that the active nature of the process of seeing, and its structured and modular character, has its pendant in the structure of visual art-which is created and evaluated by brain. Thus an inquiry into the structure of the visual brain can provide information on the nature of visual art. This is in accordance with our "structuralist approach" to study of art, and can in a way be considered as an extension and a critique of Zeki's position .
PLoS Biology, 2013
Basic and Clinical Neuroscience, 2011
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
Aesthetic Investigations, 2020
Rendiconti Lincei, 2012
Baltic Journal of Art History, 2019
Projective Processes and Neuroscience in Art and Design
(in Alfonsina Scarinzi ed. (2015) "Aesthetics and the Embodied Mind: Beyound Art Theory and the Cartesian Mind-Body Dichotomy". Springer, 229-244)
CULTURAL AND ARTS STUDIES OF NATIONAL ACADEMY OF CULTURE AND ARTS MANAGEMENT Collective monograph, 2019
Poetics Today, 2017
Frontiers in Neuroscience, 2023
Gestalt Theory, 2013
Gestalt Theory
Quantifying bodies and health. Interdisciplinary approaches, 2021
BRAIN. Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience
Journal of Comparative Literature and Aesthetics, 2024
Projective Processes and Neuroscience in Art and Design, IGI GlobalEditor: Information Science ReferenceISBN: 978-1522505105, 2016