Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
18 pages
1 file
Several philosophers of science construe models of scientic theories as set-theoretic structures. Some of them moreover claim that models should not be construed as structures in the sense of model theory because the latter are languagedependent. I argue that if we are ready to construe models as set-theoretic structures (strict semantic view), we could equally well construe them as model-theoretic structures of higher-order logic (liberal semantic view). I show that every family of set-theoretic structures has an associated language of higher-order logic and an up to signature isomorphism unique model-theoretic counterpart, which is able to serve the same purposes. This allows to carry over every syntactic criterion of equivalence for theories in the sense of the liberal semantic view to theories in the sense of the strict semantic view. Taken together, these results suggest that the recent dispute about the semantic view and its relation to the syntactic view can be resolved.
Dialectica, 2005
Based on an idea of Ajdukiewiu, a method of equifunctionality is developed to provide a formal explication of the notion of sameness of use relative to some system of rules. Given this, a set-theoretic explication of Lauener's context dependent conception of synonymy is introduced by looking at languages of propositional logic, and compared both with Ajdukiewicz's original conception and with Carnap's explication of synonymy based on his method of extension and intenrion ** Wolfson College, Oxford, GB.
2011
Abstract In this paper we discuss two approaches to the axiomatization of scientific theories in the context of the so called semantic approach, according to which (roughly) a theory can be seen as a class of models. The two approaches are associated respectively to Suppes' and to da Costa and Chuaqui's works.
The question of the semantic interpretation of higher-order logics has long been a matter of contention. Even though second-order quantification is quite natural, entangled interpretations have famously caused philosophers of logic such as Quine to reject second-order logic completely. In this paper I take a liberal attitude, open to maximizing the scope of logic, but careful to avoid conflation with other disciplines – and to avoid epistemological confusion. Higher-order logic (HOL) is perfectly acceptable, but one should be careful as to which semantics deserves to be called " standard ".
2004
In this paper we study categories of theories and interpretations. In these categories, notions of sameness of theories, like synonymy, bi-interpretability and mutual interpretability, take the form of isomorphism. We study the usual notions like monomorphism and product in the various theories. We provide some examples to separate notions across categories. In contrast, we show that, in some cases, notions in different categories do coincide. E.g., we can, under such-and-such conditions, infer synonymity of two theories from their being equivalent in the sense of a coarser equivalence relation. We illustrate that the categories offer an appropriate framework for conceptual analysis of notions. For example, we provide a ‘coordinate free’ explication of the notion of axiom scheme. Also we give a closer analysis of the object-language/ meta-language distinction. Our basic category can be enriched with a form of 2-structure. We use this 2-structure to characterize a salient subclass of...
In the paper we consider the classical logicism program restricted to first-order logic. The main result of this paper is the proof of the theorem, which contains the necessary and sufficient conditions for a mathematical theory to be reducible to logic. Those and only those theories, which don't impose restrictions on the size of their domains, can be reduced to pure logic. Among such theories we can mention the elementary theory of groups, the theory of combinators (combinatory logic), the elementary theory of topoi and many others. It is interesting to note that the initial formulation of the problem of reduction of mathematics to logic is principally insoluble. As we know all theorems of logic are true in the models with any number of elements. At the same time, many mathematical theories impose restrictions on size of their models. For example, all models of arithmetic have an infinite number of elements. If arithmetic was reducible to logic, it would had finite models, including an one-element model. But this is impossible in view of the axiom 0 ̸ = x ′ .
In this paper we present a unified approach to three topics: structures, formal languages and models. We begin by presenting a general theory of set theoretical structures. Formal languages and models are both structures inside this framework. We also present the link between languages and models given through a set theoretical predicate in the style of Suppes. The association of languages with structures satisfying certain conditions (given by set theoretical predicates) allow us to present an interesting application of the resulting framework: one is now able to characterize rigorously some classes of models. The classes of models so characterized play the role of scientific theories according to a version of the semantic approach to scientific theories. This is a first step in making explicit some of the underlying assumptions of the semantic approach to theories. In the end we give the example of how particle mechanics may be viewed as a theory according to that approach inside our framework.
Synthese, 2014
First, I discuss the older "theory-centered" and the more recent semantic conception of scientific theories. I argue that these two perspectives are nothing more than terminological variants of one another. I then offer a new theory-centered view of scientific theories. I argue that this new view captures the insights had by each of these earlier views, that it's closer to how scientists think about their own theories, and that it better accommodates the phenomenon of inconsistent scientific theories. Keywords Semantic conception of scientific theories • Inconsistent theories • Formal languages • Scientific theories as models • Bridge principles
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2021
Often philosophers, logicians, and mathematicians employ a notion of intended structure when talking about a branch of mathematics. In addition, we know that there are foundational mathematical theories that can find representatives for the objects of informal mathematics. In this paper, we examine how faithfully foundational theories can represent intended structures, and show that this question is closely linked to the decidability of the theory of the intended structure. We argue that this sheds light on the trade-off between expressive power and meta-theoretic properties when comparing first-order and second-order logic.
Proceedings of the 14th Meeting on the Mathematics of Language (MoL 2015), 2015
We discuss the model theory of two popular approaches to lexical semantics and their relation to transcendental logic.
2010
Abstract. A theory is stable up to ∆ if any ∆-type over a model has a few extensions up to complete types. I prove that a theory has no the independence property iff it is stable up to some ∆, where each ϕ(x; ¯y) ∈ ∆ has no the independence property. Definability of one-types over a model of a stable up to ∆ theory is investigated. 1.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
Journal of Symbolic Logic, 2004
synthese, 2020
Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 1985
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2014
Proceedings of the 8th conference on Computational linguistics -, 1980
Philosophical Studies, 2013
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2013