Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
Aristotle reasonably claims that in order to make right ethical choices, a mind must be trained to competently employ the discourse (lógos) in which ethical questions are posed and discussed. This discourse must include predications of ethical qualities such as good, bad, just, unjust, courageous, cowardly, etc. In this paper we show how Aristotle distinguishes various senses of predication, and uses these distinctions to resolve aporias in ethical discourse. An impoverished form of ethical discourse incapable of predicating qualities is described. In an appendix, the question whether ethical discourse can be divided into specialized roles that work together to reach ethical decisions is raised and discussed.
Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 2000
An Aristotelian conception of practical ethics can be derived from the account of practical reasoning that Aristotle articulates in his Rhetoric and this has important implications for the way we understand the nature and limits of practical ethics. An important feature of this conception of practical ethics is its responsiveness to the complex ways in which agents form and maintain
Philosophy and Rhetoric, 2008
Readers of this journal are likely to be familiar with Eugene Garver's 1994 Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character. Th e main claim advanced in that important book is that for Aristotle rhetoric is an art because it has internal norms and ends. From this, it follows that although any red-blooded rhetor probably does aim at winning a case, advancing a political career, getting rich, and other external goals, what is artful in rhetorical craft (technikos), and hence expressive of the distinctive human capacity for human rationality, is timely argumentation that binds premises to actionable conclusions through displays of good character and apt emotional response. Th is ordered combination of ethos, pathos, and logos recruits, or if you will interpellates, an audience that is uniquely capable of judging cases, proposals, and performances reasonably. In this way Aristotle defends rhetoric as a genuine art-an intellectual virtue-against Plato's Gorgias. To arrive at this conclusion Garver draws more widely on other parts of the Aristotelian corpus than rhetorical scholars normally do. In particular, he contrasts external with internal ends by using Aristotle's metaphysical distinction between movements, processes, or behaviors (kineseis), of which the world is chock-full, and actualizations or realizations (energeiai) of capacities, which are more rare. Because rhetorical art, qua artful, is an actualization, Garver infers that it is a "practical art" and so brushes up closely against ethical-political praxis.
Choice Reviews Online, 1999
This article discusses the feedback on students' ethics essays provided by eight markers in the Faculty of Medical Sciences at Newcastle University. It highlights significant shortcomings, including failures to identify instances where students had failed to select and to conclude on ethical issues (clearly), logical errors, misunderstandings of ethical arguments made in the literature, instances of simple deference, and a lack of critical engagement with relevant literature. Markers also made a large number of linguistic errors and, on many occasions, failed to explain clearly what they meant. Some indication is given of what the cost of this might be to health care students as well as to those who are affected by the quality of their ethical decisions. The article concludes by providing some guidance on how this cost might be reduced at Newcastle University as well as in many other institutions where similar problems are likely to exist.
This paper examines what Aristotle means when he indicates in NE I.3 that we must rest content with ethical principles that have an outline status. I motivate and explore two alternative interpretations. The first construes the outline principles as outline definitions, i.e. definitions that fail to describe the essences of ethical phenomena in terms familiar by nature. The second interprets the outline principles as sketchy or incomplete guidelines for action. I ultimately defend the second interpretation and draw out what implications it has for the precision of Aristotle’s ethical theory. I conclude by emphasizing that my preferred interpretation does not imply that Aristotle is a particularist about ethical principles.
Philosophy in review, 1997
researchgate.net
Ancient Philosophy Today, 2019
Elizabeth Anscombe and Mary Midgley discussed Aristotle’s ethics as an alternative to modern moral philosophy. This idea is best known from Anscombe’s 1958 paper ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’. The mainstream response has been to design a normative theory of ‘virtue ethics’ to rival deontology and consequentialism. This essay argues that that response is inadequate; it misses Anscombe’s point and obscures various aspects of Aristotle’s ethics, in particular his emphasis on friendship and human interconnectedness. This element of Aristotelianism was favoured by Midgley. By returning to Midgley, with the support of Aristotle, it is possible to find an alternative modern Aristotelianism in ethics.
Academy of Athens, 2018
There is an enormous scholarly discussion on how virtue of character or ethical virtue and phronesis, which is a dianoetic virtue, are related. In the present paper, I am interested in how, according to Aristotle, we develop ourselves into virtuous agents, that is, how we should train ourselves, or how we should be trained, so that we become virtuous, that is, acquire virtue of character and thus act virtuously. By taking this starting point, I will appoach the question of the relation between phronesis and virtue of character in determining virtuous action from a different angle, namely that of ethical upbringing.
S. Tenenbaum (ed.), Moral Psychology: Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and Humanities, 2007
2021
The title of this work does not refer to any lost work of the Stagirite, but to a compendium of ethical content that is well known but perhaps, in my opinion, has not been given due attention. On the other hand, the title is a verbal play on a well-known treatise pompously called, it is not clear why, the "great Ethics", Magna Moralia, admittedly late and belonging not to Aristotle himself but to members of his school from the Hellenistic period.
This is the Introduction to my book, Aristotle's Method in Ethics: Philosophy in Practice.
This thesis develops an account of ethical discourse through a unified approach to ethical evaluation, practical reasoning, and action explanation. It pursues a comparative analysis with respect to modern moral theories, theories of practical reasoning, and action theories so as to explain how a unified approach can resolve the chronic problems in each area.
2006
ἄνευ γὰρ φίλων οὐδεὶς ἕλοιτ᾽ ἂν ζῆν, ἔχων τὰ λοιπὰ ἀγαθὰ πάντα Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics VIII 1 (1155a) In Homage to José García López φιλίας χάριν Summary: The paper aims to raise certain questions of Aristotelian Ethics focusing mainly on the Nicomachean Ethics, it being the author's purpose to "contextualize" Aristotle's ethical thought and his writings on it. In the first place the structure and the links between the different books, which prove a late conflation of NE, are analyzed. Secondly, regards content, the sources of Aristotle after his rejection of Platonic Ethics are taken into consideration: these reveal a partial return to the aristocratic morals in the concepts both of eudaimonia and areté, and through the catalogue of virtues in Book IV. Finally, problems both lexical and semantic of Aristotle's ethic vocabulary are raised.
Phronesis-a Journal for Ancient Philosophy, 1997
We may distinguish two very different ways in which Aristotle figures in contemporary Anglo-American moral philosophizing. Some philosophers find in Aristotle an ethical theory that conceptualizes the subject matter of ethics, and the very questions an ethical theory should aim to answer, in ways that are crucially different from those characteristic of modem moral theories. Other philosophers view Aristotle as essentially toiling in the same philosophical fields as the modems, deploying essentially the same concepts and giving analyses of those concepts that can be compared with, and perhaps preferred to, modem analyses, without undue risk of comparing apples and oranges or of changing the subject. The title of Susan Sauve Meyer's Aristotle on Moral Responsibility' already suggests that she belongs to the second camp, and she makes it clear from the beginning of her work that she sees herself as opposing those who hold (Bernard Williams is foremost in her mind) that there is nothing in Aristotle's ethical theory corresponding to the modern notion of moral responsibility. She aims to show, on the contrary, that "Aristotle's concerns and aims in his various discussions of voluntariness are precisely those of a theorist of moral responsibility" (3). Nevertheless in the course of her masterly execution of this project M. takes care to point out that, on her reconstruction, Aristotle's theory of moral responsibility lacks at least one feature that is widely, if not universally, thought to belong to moral responsibility: what M. refers to as "responsibility for character." There is little to be gained by debating whether this feature, if it is indeed a central feature of most modem accounts of moral responsibility, is essential to the very concept of moral responsibility, or simply a feature of many modem conceptions of it (to use Rawls's distinction); we may be grateful to M. for undertaking to show that Aristotle has a notion bearing a strong family resemblance to that of moral responsibility in the modern sense. M. defends her thesis with a cogently-reasoned argument that draws not only on the three ethical treatises in the Aristotelian corpus (she rightly treats the Magna Moralia as a fairly reliable source of Aristotelian thought, th ough probably not by Aristotle's own hand) but also, and importantly, on discussions of efficient causation in Aristotle's theoretical works. On the basis of these texts M.
Review of the contents of the Proceedings of the Symposium Aristotelicum on Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics VII in Venice 2007. Published in Rhizai VIII, 1, pp. 99-109. (2011)
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.