Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
1987, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour
AI
This paper explores the metaphor of viewing computers as persons, arguing for its relevance in understanding the evolving relationship between humans and technology. It discusses the implications of assigning autonomy and responsibility to computers without sufficient consideration, juxtaposing this view with the traditional perspective that often reduces human capabilities to mere machines. By suggesting that the person metaphor can elevate the standards of computer technology rather than diminish humanity's worth, the author advocates for a more nuanced perspective that influences both technological development and societal understanding.
2009
The prevailing computer technologies, having inevitably shaped our activity and surroundings, have also pervaded human thoughts, feelings, language and self-perception. The interaction between the human being and the computer has become so close and all-embracing, that the difference between human and machine is hard to pinpoint and in some cases ceases to exist. This interrelation is well reflected in language, which demonstrates the diffusion of computing terms applied to human thoughts, processes and interactions – and vice versa. A person with exceptional memory or calculation skills has “a computer in his/her brain” or forgetting unimportant things is “deleting unnecessary files” in one’s mind. On the other hand, a computer’s central processing unit is its “brain”, a computer can put itself to “sleep” and computers interchanging data are “talking to” each other. The crossed meanings result from metaphorical mappings, which, in the tradition of Cognitive Metaphor Theory, are def...
Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 2010
Verba Vitae, 2024
The meaning of personhood in the context of AI and AI-driven systems is a topic attracting huge amounts of attention from philosophers, social scientists and legal scholars. The current discussions tend in not one, but two implicit directions regarding AI and personhood. On the one hand is the question of whether we should assign personhood to AI systems, and if so, how and when should we do this. The other direction has to do with our notion of personhood, specifically as human nature and being and its implications in a world of AI systems. I will briefly lay out some of the positions taken on this complex topic and show that a Christian theological perspective using the concept of imago dei can shed fruitful insights in this important area.
AI & Society (Springer), 2019
Since the emergence of the innovative field of artificial intelligence (AI) in the 1960s, the late Hubert Dreyfus insisted on the ontological distinction between man and machine, human and artificial intelligence. In the different editions of his classic and influential book What computers can't do (1972), he posits that an algorithmic machine can never fully simulate the complex functioning of the human mind—not now, nor in the future. Dreyfus' categorical distinctions between man and machine are still relevant today, but their relation has become more complex in our increasingly data-driven society. We, humans, are continuously immersed within a technological universe, while at the same time ubiquitous computing, in the words of computer scientist Mark Weiser, " forces computers to live out here in the world with people " (De Souza e Silva, 2006, p 20). Dreyfus' ideas are therefore challenged by thinkers such as Weiser, Kevin Kelly, Bruno Latour, Philip Agre, and Peter Paul Verbeek, who all argue that humans are much more intrinsically linked to machines than the original dichotomy suggests—they have evolved in concert. Through a discussion of the classical concepts of individuum and 'authenticity' within Western civilization, this paper argues that within the ever-expanding data-sphere of the twenty-first century, a new concept of man as 'aggregate of data' has emerged, which further erodes and undermines the categorical distinction between man and machine. This raises political and ethical questions beyond the confines of technology and artificial intelligence. Moreover, this seemingly never-ending debate on what computers should (or should not) do provokes the philosophical necessity to once again define the concept of what it is to be 'human.' Keywords Hubert Dreyfus · Artificial intelligence (AI) · Man as 'aggregate of data' · Individuality · Authenticity · Philosophy and ethics
2012
As technology continues to progress beyond the limits of what was once thought impossible, questions concerning the state of the human dominate Western thought. However, while the lines between 'human' and 'nonhuman' are perpetually disintegrating, the human seems reluctant to move beyond humanist paradigms that deploy notions of 'essence' as both a unique human quality, and the justification of immobilising the value of nonhuman species in a dichotomous hierarchical structure. How can the human reconcile their position at the top of any hierarchy when the species-boundaries are blurred in the wake of posthuman technologies that seek to enhance and alter the mythos of the pure human form? This article argues that a recalibration of contemporary conceptions of the human is required in order to account for posthuman technologies. Deploying the notion of the contemporary human as cyborgic in nature, this article examines the role played by technologies of body modification in the disruption to hegemonic narratives of the human, specifically regarding disability, gender, sexuality and subjectivity. Article The term 'human' has been constantly defined and questioned, examined and reexamined by philosophers and scholars since Socrates and Plato established early critical thinking. Despite this, there has nonetheless never been an accurate definition-or explanation-of what it is, exactly, to be human. Of course, there have been significant attempts-notably Martin Heidegger, who examined the human in relation to what it was/is not, and relentlessly pursued the notion that the human exists atop a hierarchy of life as a result of the human's possession of 'essence'. Heidegger examines the concept of essence mostly in relation the human, and also technology. This in itself problematises the uniqueness of the human based on essence. Heidegger's preoccupation regarding essence is tracing the roots of the word. According to the translation of Martin Heidegger's The Question Concerning Technology by William Lovitt, "'[e]ssence' is the traditional translation of the German noun Wesen" (1977:3, emphasis in original). In the same essay, Heidegger seeks to reveal Wesen as a verb, "with its meaning 'to dwell', provides one integral component in the meaning of the verb sein (to be)" (1977: 4, emphasis in original). Ultimately, his definition of essence equates to the German word Dasein; as just established, sein means 'to be' and Da in German translates into 'there'. "The title Dasein taken literally, therefore, means to be there, there being" (Fuller 1990: 51,
The doctrine that man is a machine was argued most forcefully in 1751 by de La Mettrie; long before the theory of evolution became generally accepted. The theory of evolution gave the problem an even sharper edge, by suggesting there may be no clear distinction between living matter and dead matter. Mettrie's doctrine that man is a machine, has more defenders than before among physicists, biologists, and philosophers; especially in the form of the thesis, that the mind is just a computer.
Schütz is clear about his major break with phenomenological philosophyp. 'as we proceed to our study of the social world, we abandon the strictly phenomenological method. […] One central idea is that the researcher should, in order to understand the person or persons she is studying, try to grasp what phenomenologist call 'meaning structure'. This notion refers to the web of meanings that are mutually constituted. Meanings, in other words, come in structures and attain meaning in relation to other meanings, not in isolation. This process of meaning constitution is largely a social process, which means that the researcher who is interested in this must study it when people interact (ASPERS, 2004, p. 3-4). To begin to understand this network of meanings the first research question in this section is: things are different objects? Why it is important to make this distinction? This differentiation is needed to define what exists in the natural world and in the artificial world of human being-made objects (BATESON, 1996). It is relevant to understanding social agents meaning level. Because, on these bases we can one make the research inference about the things and the objects. Since point of view of Gadamer some element is 'recognize as something' when its essence has been grasped
The query perseveres and undeniably grows whether the computer will make it easier or harder for human beings to tell who they really are, to ascertain their real problems, to respond more Accurately to beauty, to place adequate value on life, and to make their world safer than it now is.
Verbum et Ecclesia, 2025
The question of being human is shaped by our contexts. The emergence of artificial intelligence (AI) technologies is drastically impacting our contexts and relationships, leaving us with questions about who we are and what our roles are in the experience of daily life. This article explores some of the concepts and conversations raised by Cornel W. du Toit and furthers these thoughts considering recent developments in the science of AI. This article offers some reflection on the discourse between science and religion.
Academic Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies, 2019
One of the answers to the question of the human nature was provided by the mystical philosophers such as Ibn 'Arabī through the theory of divine form of human being. This theory in Judeo-Christian tradition is known as imago Dei. It means God created human being in His image/form. The main effort of the scholars in both Judeo-Christian and Islamic tradition has been to interpret the imago Dei and to find an explanation for man-God relationship. The present paper indicated that the meaning and functions of the theory could be understood in the light of philosophical investigations on the artificial intelligence. The paper outlined the wish of God to be seen outside of His Essence in His 'image' (human) based on Ibn'Arabī's interpretation. Then, we indicated that human being similarly tries to find the 'other' outside of his being, AI-based machines, to see his potentialities in his form (machines). Man can know himself through other (machine) which has similarities with him. We argued that this investigation helps to understand more explicit meaning of the theory and the goal of creation of the human being based on the interpretation of imago Dei in Ibn'Arabī's perspective. Therefore, the aim of the paper is to provide a comprehensible meaning of imago Dei based on Ibn 'Arabī's interpretation regarding the philosophical bases of the need for AI-based machines. The method that used for this investigation is the conceptual analysis; also, we considered pluridisciplinary which opens new possibilities of understanding of the meanings in art and philosophy.
2003
Could interaction design learn or benefit from looking at human interaction? Ewan Klein believes research into the fine-grain of human-human interaction could offer potentially valuable insights, and in this article he explains why. He also raises questions about trust and accountability in dealing with 'invisible'artefacts.
Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science, 2023
From the middle of the twentieth-century onwards, there has been a growing emphasis on the importance of relationality in what it means to be human, which we call a "relational turn." This is found in various domains, including philosophical psychology, psychoanalysis, and theological anthropology. Many have seen a close connection between relationality and personhood. In the second half of the article, we consider the implications of this trend for artificial intelligence (AI) and robotics. So far, AI has largely neglected relational intelligence, though that could perhaps be about to change. Cybernetics was rendered more open to assumptions about the contextuality of intelligence by its rather different assumptions from AI. Social robotics increasingly requires relational intelligence, and promising steps might be found in computational modeling of human relationships. Questions about whether robots can achieve personhood are difficult to resolve, though the possibility should not be ruled out.
Discussing Borders, Escaping Traps: Transdisciplinary and Transspatial Approaches, 2019
Man is a peculiar being, but what are the boundaries between human beings and machines? Many attempts at demarcating humanity, and by that identifying what makes us special, have been made throughout history. These debates are important, because they have implications for questions of both morality and politics. Even more so, it is important today because artificial beings now imitate just about all facets of humanity. This chapter examines various candidates for criteria of demarcation, such as reason, understanding, emotions, etc., and evaluates their merit. In this process, old debates of a similar character are briefly examined – debates regarding the question of what sets man apart from animals.
Neural Network World
Artificial Intelligence, 1987
W. Achtner, J. Dittmer, A. Haag, et al, 2006
2000
The mind of an individual as a system of realities. (The computational revolution and spirit in exile). Abstract This paper is about the structure, the function and the development of the individual mind. Usually, the mind was considered within one of the two modes: ...
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.