Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2004, Philosophy of Science, vol. 71, no. 4
…
19 pages
1 file
AI-generated Abstract
The paper explores Karl Popper's philosophical evolution, focusing on his early inductivism and the significant shift in his views towards falsifiability. It examines Popper's foundational works and the impact of his experiences on his theories, highlighting both historical context and the philosophical implications of his departure from induction to a more critical rationalist perspective. Through a brief analysis of Popper's thesis writings, the paper emphasizes the role of empirical data in shaping his scientific philosophy.
Karl Popper, as a critical rationalist, was an opponent of all forms of skepticism, conventionalism and relativism in science. A major argument of Popper is Hume's critique of induction, arguing that induction should never be used in science. But he disagrees with the skepticism associated with Hume, nor with the support of Bacon and Newton's pure "observation" as a starting point in the formation of theories, as there are no pure observations that do not imply certain theories. Instead, Popper proposes falsifiability as a method of scientific investigation. DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.11481.36967
The very title of my paper may cause many eyebrows to be raised. For anyone who is familiar with Popper's philosophy of science knows well that he distinguished clearly between two types of historical processes, namely, the process of conceiving a new scientific theory or idea and the methods of examining it logically, and asserted that the task of the philosophers is not to ponder on these actual thinking processes whereby a new scientific theory comes into being. The logical analysis of scientific knowledge, instead, is restricted to an examination of contents of linguistically formulated scientific theories and of the post-generational evaluative procedures of scientists. One might naturally ask what then the point behind an inquiry like this is since Popper himself was mainly concerned with post-generational justification and bequeathed the detailed study of theory creation to the psychologists and the historians. There are two principal reasons which motivated this examination. Firstly, what is generally found as the Popperian notion of creativity and scientific discovery in the literature of philosophy of science is reasonably different from what closer readings of his earlier and later works reveal. Secondly, an analysis like this can illuminate problems of theory change and scientific progress, which undoubtedly are important to philosophy of science in general and Popper in particular. This implies a crucial point, namely, that progress of scientific knowledge, contrary to what philosophers of science generally used to believe, is not the subject matter of a single discipline. In this paper I attempt to make apparent the shortcomings that the disciplinary splitting of the topic of advancement of knowledge (in science) entails.
As the title of this article indicates, its aim is to investigate in the origins of Karl Popper’s philosophy of science. In particular, find out the roots of what for him were at the time the two fundamental problems of the theory of knowledge. Thus, the fundamental questions in this work are: 1. What did Popper know of European philosophers of science that he mentions and criticizes? 2. Where does Popper's anti-inductivism and falsificationism come from? 3. Were Popper's basic positions original? 4. To what extent was Popper in his beginnings a realist philosopher? 5. How contributed Popper to the theory of scientific explanation? 6. What does contemporary scientific instrumentalism owe to Popper? Even if reading this article may cast some doubts on the solidity of Popper's basic approaches, what is indubitable is that Popper is an indispensable figure in the contemporary philosophy of science.
2013
Abstract: The very title of my paper may cause many eyebrows to be raised. For anyone who is familiar with Popper’s philosophy of science knows well that he distinguished clearly between two types of historical processes, namely, the process of conceiving a new scientific theory or idea and the methods of examining it logically, and asserted that the task of the philosophers is not to ponder on these actual thinking processes whereby a new scientific theory comes into being. The logical analysis of scientific knowledge, instead, is restricted to an examination of contents of linguistically formulated scientific theories and of the post-generational evaluative procedures of scientists. One might naturally ask what then the point behind an inquiry like this is since Popper himself was mainly concerned with post-generational justification and bequeathed the detailed study of theory creation to the psychologists and the historians. There are two principal reasons which motivated this ex...
Principia, 2014
In this paper I intend to thoroughly analyse Karl Popper's relation to metaphysics. I start with his first writings, where he states the differences between science, pseudoscience and metaphysics. I then describe how his thoughts on the subject evolved to culminate in his reflection on metaphysical research programmes and the need for a revival of natural philosophy. A major concern is Popper's famous testability criterion to set apart science from non-science. I point at the problems of the conception of metaphysics as non-testable theories (which are similar to the problems of the conception of metaphysics as theories involving unobservables) and, in order to avoid these problems, I propose to retain nothing but the traditional conception of metaphysics as the general theories about the nature of the world. This leads me to the conclusion that science is not only an empirical task but also, and in a very important sense, a speculative one.
Unlike almost all other philosophers of science, Karl Popper sought to contribute to natural philosophy or cosmology – a synthesis of science and philosophy. I consider his contributions to the philosophy of science and quantum theory in this light. There is, however, a paradox. Popper’s most famous contribution – his principle of demarcation – in driving a wedge between science and metaphysics, serves to undermine the very thing he professes to love: natural philosophy or cosmology. I argue that Popper’s philosophy of science is, in this respect, defective. Science cannot proceed without making highly problematic metaphysical assumptions concerning the comprehensibility and knowability of the universe. Precisely because these assumptions are problematic, rigour requires that they be subjected to sustained critical scrutiny, as an integral part of science itself. Popper’s principle of demarcation must be rejected. Metaphysics and philosophy of science become a vital part of science. Natural philosophy is reborn.
1972
This paper considers objections to Popper's views on scientific method. It is argued that criticism of Popper's views, developed by Kuhn, Feyerabend, and Lakatos, are not too damaging, although they do require that Popper's views be modified some¬what. It is argued that a much more serious criticism is that Popper has failed to provide us with any reason for holding that the methodological rules he advocates give us a better hope of realizing the aims of science than any other set of rules. Con¬sequently, Popper cannot adequately explain why we should value scientific theories more than other sorts of theories ; which in turn means that Popper fails to solve adequately his fundamental problem, namely the problem of demarcation. It is sug¬gested that in order to get around this difficulty we need to take the search for explana¬tions as a fundamental aim of science.
forthcoming in Philosophy of Science, ed. Eran Asoulin., 2021
Introduction to Karl Popper's philosophy of science.
This article provides an appraisal of Popper’s criticism of L. E. J. Brouwer’s intuitionist mathematics. Despite the extensive scholarship on Popper, his engagement with Brouwer’s thought has largely been overlooked. Through his critical engagement with Brouwer, Popper provides an eloquent overview of some of the innovative features of his own later objectivist evolutionary epistemology. For Brouwer, the intuitional ground of mathematics completely separates mathematics from mathematical language. Intuitionistic mathematics is an essentially languageless activity of the mind. The mathematician is prioritised as the ultimate source of authority over the formalised representation of mathematics. Popper, while appreciating the important role of intuitions in identifying problems and deriving solutions was highly critical of Brouwer’s subjectivist orientation. Popper reconstructed the problem of intuition in terms of evolutionary cognition as the problem of “unconscious expectations” or “background knowledge”. This background knowledge does not derive from some pristine source of truth in the subject, but is the result of previous problem solving attempts, which become built into our cognitive apparatus and unconsciously inform our actions in the form of conjectures. What is crucial for Popper, is the way we externalise our knowledge in the form of conjectures, which both enables it to be criticised, as well as potentially lay bare hitherto unseen implications. For Popper, this was crucial to the way knowledge grows, and is necessary for the development of the self, which is dependent upon linguistic communication.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 1985
American Psychologist, 1985
Karl Popper: Critical Appraisals
CENTRAL ASIAN JOURNAL OF LITERATURE, PHILOSOPHY AND CULTURE, 2022
Presented at 'Technology, Knowledge, Truth' Conference held by the Melbourne Society for Continental Philosophy, Dec. 13-15th 2017
SSRN Electronic Journal, 2000
JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY AND DEVELOPMENT, 2017
History of European Ideas, 2011
Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 2003
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 1993
Philosophy Study, 2013
Journal for General Philosophy of Science - Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, 1988
Journal of The Operational Research Society, 2009