Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
7 pages
1 file
Hilbert's program modi ed.
The study of the foundations of mathematics is in a crisis: the failure of logicism has invited a satisfactory alternative. This should be a better proof theory; Gentzen's natural deduction came to provide this but had a limited success. The discussion on this practically faded out. Solomon Feferman and his coworkers propose tentatively a synthesis that relies on achievements from diverse directions. Presenting sympathetically ideas of Hilbert, Brouwer, Gentzen, Weyl, and Bishop, they hope to change in the standard textbooks of logic. This requires a more problem-oriented presentatlon of the background material that should make the situation more accessible to the ordinary philosophy faculty. 'Ihk invites supplementary discussions of achievements that they are thus far sadly overlooked, especially those of Popper, Robinson, and Lakatos.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 2019
A short text in the hand of David Hilbert, discovered in Göttingen a century after it was written, shows that Hilbert had considered adding a 24th problem to his famous list of mathematical problems of the year 1900. The problem he had in mind was to find criteria for the simplicity of proofs and to develop a general theory of methods of proof in mathematics. In this paper, it is discussed to what extent proof theory has achieved the second of these aims. This article is part of the theme issue ‘The notion of ‘simple proof’ - Hilbert's 24th problem’.
Studia Logica, 2018
I see the question what it is that makes an inference valid and thereby gives a proof its epistemic power as the most fundamental problem of general proof theory. It has been surprisingly neglected in logic and philosophy of mathematics with two exceptions: Gentzen's remarks about what justifies the rules of his system of natural deduction and proposals in the intuitionistic tradition about what a proof is. They are reviewed in the paper and I discuss to what extent they succeed in answering what a proof is. Gentzen's ideas are shown to give rise to a new notion of valid argument. At the end of the paper I summarize and briefly discuss an approach to the problem that I have proposed earlier.
Philosophy Compass, 2010
A variety of projects in proof theory of relevance to the philosophy of mathematics are surveyed, including Gödel's incompleteness theorems, conservation results, independence results, ordinal analysis, predicativity, reverse mathematics, speed-up results, and provability logics.
This is a survey of some of the principal developments in proof theory from its inception in the 1920s, at the hands of David Hilbert, up to the 1960s. Hilbert's aim was to use this as a tool in his nitary consistency program to eliminate the \actual in nite" in mathematics from proofs of purely nitary statements. One of the main approaches that turned out to be the most useful in pursuit of this program was that due to Gerhard Gentzen, in the 1930s, via his calculi of \sequents" and his Cut-Elimination Theorem for them. Following that we t r a c e how and why prima facie in nitary concepts, such as ordinals, and in nitary methods, such as the use of in nitely long proofs, gradually came to dominate proof-theoretical developments.
David Hilbert's Lectures on the Foundations of Arithmetic and Logic 1917-1933, 2013
Proof Technology in Mathematics Research and Teaching, 2019
Following Hilbert, there seems to be a simple and clear definition of mathematical proof: it is a sequence of formulae each of which is either an axiom or follows from earlier formulae by a rule of inference. Automated theorem provers are based on this Hilbertian concept of proof, in which the formulae and rules of inference are represented in a formal logic. These logicbased proofs are typically an order of magnitude longer than the rigorous proofs produced by human mathematicians. There is a consensus, however, that rigorous proofs could, in principle, be unpacked into logical proofs, but this programme is rarely carried out because it would be tedious and uninformative. We argue that, for at least one class of rigorous proofs, which we will call schematic proofs, such a simple unpacking is not available. We will illustrate schematic proofs by analysing Cauchy's faulty proof of Euler's Theorem V-E+F = 2, as reported in [Lakatos, 1976] and giving further examples from [Nelsen, 1993]. We will then give a logic-based account of schematic proofs, distinguishing them from Hilbertian proofs, and showing why they are error prone.
2006
of accuracy. On the other hand, the constructivist claims that to know that a particular sequence of rational numbers converges is to know how to approximate the corresponding real number to an arbitrarily given degree of accuracy. Hence the constructivist rejects the law of excluded middle. Using the law of excluded middle one can also argue that every sequence of rational numbers that does not converge must diverge. However, one can not from the knowledge that a particular sequence of rational numbers does not converge construct the corresponding witness. The example just given illustrates the direct nature of constructive existence, as opposed to the indirect nature of classical existence, and shows why the law of excluded middle is not accepted as a law of constructive logic. Finally, I would like to thank my supervisor, Per Martin-Löf, for posing the problem of investigating how the double-negation interpretation operates on derivations and not only on formulas as well as for his continued guidance of my work. Without him, this thesis would never have come into existence. Jens Brage Reynolds (1972), and Plotkin (1975) for the foundations of CPS translations and Reynolds (1993) for the early history of continuations. To my knowledge there is no interpretation of classical logic in constructive logic that makes full use of the syntactic-semantic method of constructive type theory. With this thesis I hope to fill this gap. The subject of interpretations of classical logic in constructive logic began with the double negation interpretation of classical logic in minimal logic due to Kolmogorov (1925). The double negation interpretation was then followed by the interpretation of Peano arithmetic in Heyting arithmetic due to Gödel (1933) and the interpretation of classical logic in intuitionistic logic due to Kuroda (1951). Yet it was not until Griffin (1990) showed how to extend the formulae-as-types correspondence to classical logic that significant growth took place. His solution was to include operations on the flow of control, similar to call/cc of Scheme, into the notion of computation given by a simply typed call-by-value λ-calculus. After that Parigot (1992) introduced his λµ-calculus to realize classical proofs as programs. The λµ-calculus extended the simply typed λ-calculus with operators that can be used to model operations on the flow of control. The development then took the form of CPS translations of different λµ-calculi into different λ-calculi. See Ong (1996) and Ong and Stewart (1997) for call-by-value respectively call-byname CPS translations of Parigot's λµ-calculus into the simply typed λ-calculus. See Selinger (2001, p. 24) for an informal description of the semantics of the λµcalculus.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
Journal of Applied Logic, 2017
Mathematical Structures in Computer Science
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1974
Mathesis Universalis, Computability and Proof, 2019
Boolean Models and Methods in Mathematics, Computer Science and Engineering ed. by Crama and Hammer, Chapter 3., 2010
Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 1998
Gentzen's Centenary, 2015
Journal of Symbolic Logic, 2007
STUDIA LOGICA, vol.108(4), pp 857-875, 2020
Mathematical Society of Japan Memoirs, 1998
Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science, 2009