Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
This work proposes a rethinking of Goedel’s incomplete results; Specifically, rather than some true statements remaining unreachable for verification on a true-false basis in any axiomatic system that is strong enough to express basic arithmetic, the structure itself ensures that no statement remains unverified on a true-false basis, which is consistent with both Goedel’s results as well as Hilbert’s assertion that such algorithm does exist, albeit not one that could be derived within the separately given axiomatic system itself. A statement defined here as phenomena bridges that divide. Phenomena, defined as non-axiomatic, non-tautological, and non-contradictory statements exist invariably in any such axiomatic system, regardless of the possibility to construct them within the axiomatic system. All other non-axiomatic, non-tautological and non-contradictory statements are also defined as phenomena; Phenomena allow for incorporation of Peano arithmetic, Euclidean geometry and Real analysis into ZFT; Axiom of choice would hence be reformulated and incorporated as a theorem. Reasoning provided on why Cantor’s paradox should be included into the ZFT as an axiom. Proof of Riemann conjecture is provided through the application of phenomena.
This paper brings up some important points about logic, e.g., mathematical logic, and also an inconsistence in logic as per Gödel's incompleteness theorems which state that there are mathematical truths that are not decidable or provable. These incompleteness theorems have shaken the solid foundation of mathematics where innumerable proofs and theorems have a place of pride. The great mathematician David Hilbert had been much disturbed by them. There are much long unsolved famous conjectures in mathematics, e.g., the twin primes conjecture, the Goldbach conjecture, the Riemann hypothesis, etc. Perhaps, by Gödel's incompleteness theorems the proofs for these famous conjectures will not be possible and the numerous mathematicians attempting to find the solutions for these conjectures are simply banging their heads against the metaphorical wall. Besides mathematics, Gödel's incompleteness theorems will have ramifications in other areas involving logic. This paper looks at the ramifications of the incompleteness theorems, which pose the serious problem of inconsistency, and offers a solution to this dilemma. The paper also looks into the apparent inconsistence of the axiomatic method in mathematics. [Published in international mathematics journal. Acknowledgments: The author expresses his gratitude to the referees and the Editor-in-Chief for their valuable comments in strengthening the contents of this paper.]
A principle, according to which any scientific theory can be mathematized, is investigated. That theory is presupposed to be a consistent text, which can be exhaustedly represented by a certain mathematical structure constructively. In thus used, the term " theory " includes all hypotheses as yet unconfirmed as already rejected. The investigation of the sketch of a possible proof of the principle demonstrates that it should be accepted rather a metamathematical axiom about the relation of mathematics and reality. Its investigation needs philosophical means. Husserl's phenomenology is what is used, and then the conception of " bracketing reality " is modelled to generalize Peano arithmetic in its relation to set theory in the foundation of mathematics. The obtained model is equivalent to the generalization of Peano arithmetic by means of replacing the axiom of induction with that of transfinite induction. Accepting or rejecting the principle, two kinds of mathematics appear differing from each other by its relation to reality. Accepting the principle, mathematics has to include reality within itself in a kind of Pythagoreanism. These two kinds are called in paper correspondingly Hilbert mathematics and Gödel mathematics. The sketch of the proof of the principle demonstrates that the generalization of Peano arithmetic as above can be interpreted as a model of Hilbert mathematics into Gödel mathematics therefore showing that the former is not less consistent than the latter, and the principle is an independent axiom. An information interpretation of Hilbert mathematics is involved. It is a kind of ontology of information. Thus the problem which of the two mathematics is more relevant to our being (rather than reality for reality is external only to Gödel mathematics) is discussed. An information interpretation of the Schrödinger equation is involved to illustrate the above problem.
Social Science Research Network, 2022
discusses the option of the Gödel incompleteness statement (1931: whether "Satz VI" or "Satz X") to be an axiom due to the pair of the axiom of induction in arithmetic and the axiom of infinity in set theory after interpreting them as logical negations to each other. The present Part II considers the previous Gödel's paper (1930) (and more precisely, the negation of "Satz VII", or "the completeness theorem") as a necessary condition for granting the Gödel incompleteness statement to be a theorem just as the statement itself, to be an axiom. Then, the "completeness paper" can be interpreted as relevant to Hilbert mathematics, according to which mathematics and reality as well as arithmetic and set theory are rather entangled or complementary rather than mathematics to obey reality able only to create models of the latter. According to that, both papers (1930; 1931) can be seen as advocating Russell's logicism or the intensional propositional logic versus both extensional arithmetic and set theory. Reconstructing history of philosophy, Aristotle's logic and doctrine can be opposed to those of Plato or the pre-Socratic schools as establishing ontology or intensionality versus extensionality. Husserl's phenomenology can be analogically realized including and particularly as philosophy of mathematics. One can identify propositional logic and set theory by virtue of Gödel's completeness theorem (1930: "Satz VII") and even both and arithmetic in the sense of the "compactness theorem" (1930: "Satz X") therefore opposing the latter to the "incompleteness paper" (1931). An approach identifying homomorphically propositional logic and set theory as the same structure of Boolean algebra, and arithmetic as the "half" of it in a rigorous construction involving information and its unit of a bit. Propositional logic and set theory are correspondingly identified as the shared zero-order logic of the class of all first-order logics and the class at issue correspondingly. Then, quantum mechanics does not need any quantum logics, but only the relation of propositional logic, set theory, arithmetic, and information: rather a change of the attitude into more mathematical, philosophical, and speculative than physical, empirical and experimental. Hilbert's epsilon calculus can be situated in the same framework of the relation of propositional logic and the class of all mathematical theories. The horizon of Part III investigating Hilbert mathematics (i.e. according to the Pythagorean viewpoint about the world as mathematical) versus Gödel mathematics (i.e. the usual understanding of mathematics as all mathematical models of the world external to it) is outlined.
In current mathematical practice, mathematical knowledge (if it is achieved at all) is achieved by proving theorems on the basis of definitions and axioms. The problem is to understand how what is achieved thereby constitutes knowledge; more specifically, it is to develop a unified account of mathematical truth and mathematical knowledge, one that reveals their inner connection. What stands in our way, according to a very familiar argument of Benacerraf's, is that in mathematics there seems no way to combine a Tarskian semantics, according to which truth involves ineliminable reference to objects (either by way of singular terms or by way of quantifiers), with an adequate epistemology: either mathematical knowledge is by way of proof, in which case mathematical objects are irrelevant to mathematical knowledge and then we have no account of mathematical truth, or mathematical knowledge is not by way of proof because mathematical objects are constitutive of mathematical truth, but then we have no resources for understanding mathematical knowledge. I then trace the difficulties, in a series of stages, all the way down to our most basic conception of logic as formal and merely explicative: if mathematics is a practice of reasoning from concepts by logic alone then it ought, according to Kant, to be analytic, that is, merely explicative, not knowledge properly speaking at all. This, I submit, is the really hard problem of mathematical truth. Four responses are outlined, but only one holds out promise of resolving our difficulties, namely, that of Peirce and Frege. According to them, logic is a science, and hence experimental and fallible, symbolic language is contentful despite involving no reference to any objects, and proof is a constructive and hence fruitful process. Adequately developed, these ideas will enable us finally to resolve the problem of mathematical truth.
Revue internationale de philosophie, 2005
Gödel began his 1951 Gibbs Lecture by stating: "Research in the foundations of mathematics during the past few decades has produced some results which seem to me of interest, not only in themselves, but also with regard to their implications for the traditional philosophical problems about the nature of mathematics." (Gödel 1951) Gödel is referring here especially to his own incompleteness theorems (Gödel 1931). Gödel's first incompleteness theorem (as improved by Rosser (1936)) says that for any consistent formalized system F, which contains elementary arithmetic, there exists a sentence G F of the language of the system which is true but unprovable in that system. Gödel's second incompleteness theorem states that no consistent formal system can prove its own consistency. 1 These results are unquestionably among the most philosophically important logicomathematical discoveries ever made. However, there is also ample misunderstanding and confusion surrounding them. The aim of this paper is to review and evaluate various philosophical interpretations of Gödel's theorems and their consequences, as well as to clarify some confusions. I have argued for my own interpretation of Hilbert's program in detail in Raatikainen (2003a).
2020
Those incompleteness theorems mean the relation of (Peano) arithmetic and (ZFC) set theory, or philosophically, the relation of arithmetical finiteness and actual infinity. The same is managed in the framework of set theory by the axiom of choice (respectively, by the equivalent well-ordering "theorem'). One may discuss that incompleteness form the viewpoint of set theory by the axiom of choice rather than the usual viewpoint meant in the proof of theorems. The logical corollaries from that "nonstandard" viewpoint the relation of set theory and arithmetic are demonstrated.
Miscellanea Logica VI, UK FF, Praha 2006, pp. 45–64, 2006
When posing the old question ‘What are arithmetical truths about?’ (‘What is their epistemic status?’ or ‘How are they possible?’) we find ourselves standing in the shadow of Gödel, just as our predecessors stood in the shadow of Kant. Of course, this observation may be a bit misleading if only for the reason that Gödel’s famous incompleteness theorems are not of a philosophical nature, at least not in the first place. There are plenty of texts, however, explaining them as philosophically relevant, i.e. as having some philosophical implications. In this article I am not aiming to add a new interpretation to the old ones. Rather, I am proposing to see the incompleteness as a link in the chain of certain great (positive or negative) foundational results such as Frege’s calculization of logic, Russell’s paradox, G¨odel’s completeness theorem, Gentzen’s proof of consistency etc. The foundational line described in this way can then be critically examined as relatively successful with respect to some of its leading ideas and as unsuccessful with respect to others. What I have particularly in mind here is the idea of reducing arithmetic to logic, with its decisive influence on the rebirth and subsequent development of modern (mathematical) logic. Hence, the key issue of this article may be formulated as follows: ‘What do Gödel’s theorems tell us about the alleged analyticity or syntheticity of arithmetic?’.
The present first part about the eventual completeness of mathematics (called “Hilbert mathematics”) is concentrated on the Gödel incompleteness (1931) statement: weather it is an axiom rather than a theorem inferable from the axioms of (Peano) arithmetic, (ZFC) set theory, and propositional logic. The main argument consists in the contradiction of the axiom of induction in arithmetic and the axiom of infinity in set theory. Thus, the pair of arithmetic and set are similar to Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries distinguishably only by the Fifth postulate: correspondingly, by the axiom of finiteness (induction) versus that of finiteness being idempotent negations to each other. The axiom of choice transforms any set in a well-ordering either necessarily finite according to the axiom of induction or also optionally infinite according to the axiom of infinity. The Gödel incompleteness statement relies on the contradiction of the axioma of induction and infinity.
Melisa Vivanco, 2023
Some of the most influential programs in the philosophy of mathematics started from the philosophical study of natural numbers. On the one hand, our arithmetic intuitions appear earlier and more direct than other mathematical (and non-mathematical) intuitions. On the other hand, while arithmetic admits one of the first axiomatizations with wide acceptance within the mathematical practice, the study of natural numbers sets a methodological precedent that will later seek to be replicated in other areas, in particular, in the study of the most complex numerical structures. This course will address the main issues in the philosophical discussion on arithmetic. Among these topics are the ideas of the various classical doctrines on the foundations of arithmetic, from the milestone of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems to recent doctrines on the semantics of numerical expressions and arithmetic sentences. The class will cover debates about metaphysics and the epistemology of numbers and arithmetic truths.
One of the richest and most salient applications of a non-classical logic is the matter of how mathematics operates within its province. Historically, this is most evident in the case of intuitionism, insofar as the intuitionistic standpoints with respect to deduction and mathematical practice are tightly bound together. Yet even in the case of Robert Meyer's relevant arithmetic R#, that a robust and compelling theory of arithmetic can be erected on relevant foundations speaks to the maturity of relevant logics. Accordingly, as connexive logic matures as a field, the topography of mathematics against a connexive backdrop becomes more and more compelling. The contraclassicality of connexive logics entails that the development of connexive mathematics will be more complex---and, arguably, more interesting---than intuitionistic or relevant accounts. For example, although formally undecidable sentences in classical Peano arithmetic remain independent of its intuitionistic and relevant counterparts, there exist undecidable sentences of classical arithmetic that will become decidable modulo any reasonable connexive arithmetic. In, e.g., Peano arithmetic, the Gödel sentence G is undecidable. Classically, this entails that the sentence ~(G->~G) is likewise undecidable. Of course, in a connexive logic L and connexive arithmetic L#, L# will prove ~(G->~G), witnessing that some classically undecidable statements in number theory become decidable connexively. Although this example is extremely simple, it demonstrates that there are many subtle questions that uniquely arise in a connexive mathematics. In this paper, I wish to make a few comments on how mathematics---in particular, arithmetic---must behave if formulated connexively. We will first consider some relevant historical and philosophical topics, such as Łukasiewicz' number-theoretic argument against Aristotle's Thesis, before taking a foray into the formalization of modest subsystems of arithmetic in Richard Angell's PA1 and PA2, observing some of the pathologies that will greet arithmetic in these settings.
This paper investigates the relation between Carnap and Quine's views on analyticity on the one hand, and their views on philosophical analysis or explication on the other. I argue that the stance each takes on what constitutes a successful explication largely dictates the view they take on analyticity. I show that although acknowledged by neither party (in fact Quine frequently expressed his agreement with Carnap on this subject) their views on explication are substantially different. I argue that this difference not only explains their differences on the question of analyticity, but points to a Quinean way to answer a challenge that Quine posed to Carnap. The answer to this challenge leads to a Quinean view of analyticity such that arithmetical truths are analytic, according to Quine's own remarks, and set theory is at least defensibly analytic.
The conflict between Platonic realism and Constructivism marks a watershed in philosophy of mathematics. Among other things, the controversy over the Axiom of Choice is typical of the conflict. Platonists accept the Axiom of Choice, which allows a set consisting of the members resulting from infinitely many arbitrary choices, while Constructivists reject the Axiom of Choice and confine themselves to sets consisting of effectively specifiable members. Indeed there are seemingly unpleasant consequences of the Axiom of Choice. The non-constructive nature of the Axiom of Choice leads to the existence of non-Lebesgue measurable sets, which in turn yields the Banach-Tarski Paradox. But the Banach-Tarski Paradox is so called in the sense that it is a counter-intuitive theorem. To corroborate my view that mathematical truths are of non-constructive nature, I shall draw upon Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems. This also shows the limitations inherent in formal methods. Indeed the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem and the Skolem Paradox seem to pose a threat to υlatonists. In this light, Quine/υutnam's arguments come to take on a clear meaning. According to the model-theoretic arguments, the Axiom of Choice depends for its truth-value upon the model in which it is placed. In my view, however, this is another limitation inherent in formal methods, not a defect for Platonists. To see this, we shall examine how mathematical models have been developed in the actual practice of mathematics. I argue that most mathematicians accept the Axiom of Choice because the existence of non-Lebesgue measurable sets and the Well-Ordering of reals open the possibility of more fruitful mathematics. Finally, after responding to ψenacerraf's challenge to Platonism, I conclude that in mathematics, as distinct from natural sciences, there is a close connection between essence and existence. Actual mathematical theories are the parts of the maximally logically consistent theory that describes mathematical reality. 1 I will use the word-Constructivism‖ in a broader sense than ψrower's ωonstructivism. In ψrower's Constructivism mathematical entities are constructible in our mind. But I will use the word-Constructivism‖ in a narrower sense than Gödel's axiom of constructibility. Gödel's Axiom of Constructibility is a much stronger assumption than Constructivism as I call it. Choice that we couldn't otherwise. Platonists accept the Axiom of Choice, which allows a set consisting of the members resulting from infinitely many arbitrary choices, while Constructivists reject the Axiom of Choice and confine themselves to sets consisting of effectively specifiable members (Chapter 1). Lebesgue's theory of measure will set the stage for discussing the Banach-Tarski Paradox and the existence of measurable cardinals in later chapters. Also, since Lebesgue is one of the French Constructivists, it is interesting to see the non-constructive nature of Lebesgue measure creates an irreconcilable tension with Lebesgue's skeptical attitude toward the Axiom of Choice (Chapter 2). The Hausdorff Paradox is the prototype of the Banach-Tarski Paradox. Informally, the Hausdorff Paradox states that a sphere is decomposed into finite number of pieces and reassembled by rigid motions to form two copies of almost the same size as the original. Here-almost‖ means-except on a countable subset.‖ ψanach and Tarski made improvement on the Hausdorff Paradox by eliminating the need to exclude a countable subset from a sphere. Informally, the Banach-Tarski Paradox states that a sphere is decomposed into finite number of pieces and reassembled by rigid motions to form two copies of exactly the same size as the original. The Banach-Tarski Paradox deepened the skepticism about the Axiom of Choice. But the Banach-Tarski Paradox is so called in the sense that it is a counter-intuitive theorem, as distinct from a logical contradiction or a fallacious reasoning. I argue that we should accept the Banach-Tarski Paradox as a Platonic truth and rejects epistemology based on a mathematical intuition (Chapter 3). Next, from a slightly different perspective, I corroborate my view that mathematical truths are of non-constructive nature. Once we got the undecidability of Peano Arithmetic (PA), Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem is immediate. The set of true sentences in PA is not recursively enumerable. But the set of theorems (provable sentences) in PA is recursively enumerable. So it is easy to see that there is a sentence that is true but unprovable. This implies that there are some arithmetical truths we cannot get access to in an effective way. We also have to note Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems show that there are limitations inherent in formal methods (Chapter 4).
Social Science Research Network, 2020
The paper introduces and utilizes a few new concepts: "nonstandard Peano arithmetic", "complementary Peano arithmetic", "Hilbert arithmetic". They identify the foundations of both mathematics and physics demonstrating the equivalence of the newly introduced Hilbert arithmetic and the separable complex Hilbert space of quantum mechanics in turn underlying physics and all the world. That new both mathematical and physical ground can be recognized as information complemented and generalized by quantum information. A few fundamental mathematical problems of the present such as Fermat's last theorem, four-color theorem as well as its new-formulated generalization as "four-letter theorem", Poincaré's conjecture, "P vs NP" are considered over again, from and within the newfounding conceptual reference frame of information, as illustrations. Simple or crucially simplifying solutions and proofs are demonstrated. The link between the consistent completeness of the system mathematics-physics on the ground of information and all the great mathematical problems of the present (rather than the enumerated ones) is suggested.
Benacerraf's Dilemma (BD), as formulated by Paul Benacerraf in "Mathematical Truth," is about the apparent impossibility of reconciling a "standard" (i.e., classical Platonic) semantics of mathematics with a "reasonable" (i.e., causal, spatiotemporal) epistemology of cognizing true statements. In this paper I spell out a new solution to BD. I call this new solution a positive Kantian phenomenological solution for three reasons: (1) It accepts Benacerraf's preliminary philosophical assumptions about the nature of semantics and knowledge, as well as all the basic steps of BD, and then shows how we can, consistently with those very assumptions and premises, still reject the skeptical conclusion of BD and also adequately explain mathematical knowledge. (2) The standard semantics of mathematically necessary truth that I offer is based on Kant's philosophy of arithmetic, as interpreted by Charles Parsons and by me. The reasonable epistemology of mathematical knowledge that I offer is based on the phenomenology of logical and mathematical self-evidence developed by early Husserl in Logical Investigations and by early Wittgenstein in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
It is not sufficient to supply an instance of Tarski’s schema, ⌈“p” is true if and only if p⌉ for a certain statement in order to get a definition of truth for this statement and thus fix a truth-condition for it. A definition of the truth of a statement x of a language L is a bi-conditional whose two members are two statements of a meta-language L’. Tarski’s schema simply suggests that a definition of truth for a certain segment x of a language L consists in a statement of the form: ⌈v(x) is true if and only if τ(x)⌉, where ⌈v(x)⌉ is the name of x in L’ and τ(x) is a function τ: S → S’ (S and S’ being the sets of the statements respectively of L end L’) which associates to x the statement of L’ expressed by the same sentence as that which expresses x in L. In order to get a definition of truth for x and thus fix a truth-condition for it, one has thus to specify the function τ. A conception of truth for a certain class X of mathematical statements is a general condition imposed on the truth-conditions for the statements of this class. It is advanced when the nature of the function τ is specified for the statements belonging to X. It is sober when there is no need to appeal to a controversial ontology in order to describe the conditions under which the statement τ(x) is assertible. Four sober conceptions of truth are presented and discussed.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.