Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
AI
The text discusses the limitations of traditional philosophy in the contemporary era, arguing that philosophy has become disconnected from empirical reality and increasingly irrelevant. It suggests that art may occupy a unique space after philosophy and religion, offering a form of existence that is not bound by philosophical judgments. The author posits that art's value lies in its ability to remain independent from philosophical definitions and serves as a reflection of human experience rather than a functional necessity.
The Routledge Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophy, 2008
= encouraged to lselves with the tformed manner 1ers to a nnature hical challenges :elf have learned DERMOT MORAN Britain, prominent women philosophers include: Philippa Foot, Onora O'Neill, Susan Stebbing, Sarah Waterlow Broadie; in the US: in Australia, Genevieve Lloyd. IS Women not only entered the academy to work in traditional areas, but often transformed the debate in certain areas, introduced new topics, and made ground-breaking contributions (Ruth Marcus in logic; Judith Jarvis Thomson in the area of the ethics of abortion). Following on from the theme of feminism, new areas have emerged that include issues surrounding the philosophy of gender and lately "queer theory," which has overlapped the boundaries of philosophy and linked it more with disciplines of social criticism.
In the last seventy years, the philosophical community, i.e the people professionally engaged in philosophy, has faced an immense growth, due to huge public investments in universities and research after the Second World War in Western countries [Rescher 2005, Marconi 2014]. We can say that in no other period of the history of philosophy there were so many professional philosophers as in the last fifty years, as there were not so many scientists [Price 1963]. This quantitative increase questions the historian of contemporary philosophy in multiple ways. In the present paper I would like to address the methodological issues in historiography of philosophy related to this increase. Therefore I will ask which are the concepts and methods that we should use in order to understand properly the new situation of contemporary philosophical research. In particular, I will argue that traditional concepts and assumption used in writing the history of philosophy are today just partially fit to describe the contemporary evolution of philosophy. The historical object they aim to describe is transforming in such a way that they are more an obstacle than a help to its comprehension. In order to reach this conclusion, my contribution is structured in the following way. In the first part I will provide some quantitative data about the growth of philosophical enterprise in the second half of twentieth century; secondly, I will sketch an analysis of the key notions used in the traditional everyday work of the historian of philosophy. I will focus on the very workaday " toolkit " , which comprehend notions such as " author " , " text " , " tradition " , " philosophical school " and so on. In the third part, I will present some tensions to which these very commonplace notions are subject due to the quantitative growth of philosophy. In particular, I will attempt to show how the traditional notion of " author " as the central unit of history of philosophy is partially inadequate to describe contemporary philosophy. Hence, I will suggest that quantitative methods used in contemporary studies of science, such as scientometrics and science-mapping, can in part supply this inadequacy, opening at the same time new perspectives on the development of contemporary philosophy. Finally, in the light of the previous considerations, I will reflect upon the role of this non-standard history of philosophy in contemporary philosophical research, situating my view in the debate started with the collection of essays about historiography of philosophy edited by Rorty, Schneewind and Skinner in 1984 [Rorty-Schneewind-Skinner 1984].
Philosophy and Revolutions in Genetics, 2005
Human beings are paying a dire price for disparaging philosophy in all facets of life, especially in the field of natural science where the most intelligent explorations of nature for the survival and advance of Homo sapiens species are supposed to be conducted. In the mean time, the professional discipline crowned with the title “philosophy” has been haunted by its own collective and systematic pitfalls. Consequently, despite of the apparent rapid growing global prosperity, the earth civilization is indeed walking at a fast pace down to a deep crisis. To make matters much worse, due to its intelligent challenge, the weakened collective philosophical capacity in the world is not something that can be made up with some crash courses as for scientific and technological trainings. If there were some kind interstellar competitions as claimed in some ufologist products, this hazardous trend in human mainstream philosophy would definitely put earth civilization in a scarily disadvantageous position; even if the interstellar competitions are only fairy tale, the collapse of human collective philosophical capacity would undoubtedly be hazardous for humans when facing expected or unexpected disastrous natural perils, let alone those created by humans due to the poor collective philosophical capacity. This writing will demonstrate through examples how philosophically erroneous mistakes in mathematics and physics that were made at the turn of 20th century could last for more than a century without being identified, as well as an issue that has lingered for several centuries and still confuses the whole world with its philosophical complexity. In those examples, we could see that scientists with the aura of the smartest people on earth could easily be convinced by “simple, straight, and brilliant ideas”, which could bring aesthetically attractive convenience but would lead to various kinds of false knowledge and wrong practices, and then defend those ideas with all their lives for a long time, simply because the scientific community has not been prepared with strong philosophical capacity of reasoning. In addition to the mistakes in mathematics and physics, this writing will also discuss the devastating stale status of the existing academia of philosophy as well as the need and vision of having a parallel new professional community of philosophy.
Philosophy, perhaps more than any other discipline, is fascinated by its own history. Introductory philosophy courses for undergraduates often focus on great works from the distant past by authors such as Plato and Descartes. Conferences, journals, and graduate seminars are devoted to the discussion of the history of philosophy. Philosophy departments normally include specialists on the history of philosophy. Philosophers conducting cutting edge research often take the trouble to situate their work with respect to long dead predecessors. In all of these respects, philosophy is vastly different from, for example, physics. Undergraduates are not taught physics by reading and discussing the works of Archimedes or Newton. (Of course, students are taught Newtonian mechanics, but they don't read and discuss the Principia in the way that philosophy students might study the Republic or the Meditations.) Conferences, journals and graduate seminars on the history of physics abound. But they are not normally considered part of the disciplinary activity of physics itself. Of course, disciplines, like academic departments, are not natural kinds and their organization is, to some extent, conventional. Disciplinary boundaries are thus contingent and reflect, at least to some degree, accidents of history. But they are not, for all that, entirely arbitrary. Disciplines tend to group together subject matters that are interestingly similar and academic departments often house teachers and researchers whose work bears tighter connection to each other's than to that of their cross-campus colleagues. It is striking that philosophy as a discipline takes ownership of the study of its history in a way that physics, for example, does not. Physicists conducting cutting edge research rarely take the trouble to situate their work with respect to their great predecessors from the distant past. They do not teach and study their works. And the physicists do not appear to be, in this regard, unusual. I have just checked the undergraduate teaching schedules for several leading departments of economics, mathematics, and psychology. 1
2000
I will not wax millenial. But we are nearing the end of a century. It is conceivable that its most important philosophical event will take place between now and December 31. But it is unlikely. So we are at a point where we can, not unreasonably, look back and assess the philosophical events of our century. Any philosophically respectable century has its moments; a point, or points, at which ways of thinking about problems, and about philosophy itself, change radically. Such a moment might fairly be called revolutionary, if one does not puff up that term unduly. Two revolutions in a century would be a lot. I will describe what I think is the crucial revolutionary moment in our century. I need to acknowledge that the view I will present is personal, or at least far from received wisdom. Some of you may find it biased. First, I do not think that the revolution means that philosophy is, or should be, at an end, that we are somehow in a period of 'post-philosophy', or that the idea of a philosophical problem is somehow passé. The revolution I am going to describe left us with some genuine, and severe, philosophical problems. At the end of my talk I will describe them, and hint, but no more, at a way with them-a way I do not know to be adequate, since it has not yet been tried fully. Second, it will occur to some of you that my revolution is suspiciously Anglophone, so, perhaps, parochial. If 'Anglophone' includes enough of Vienna and Berlin, and enough work written in German, then my revolution is, indeed, Anglophone. Given the political events of our century, it is not surprising that that should be so. In any event, such is life. If I thought the action were elsewhere, I would be there. The revolution I have in mind can be dated as occurring between 1930 and 1960 (interrupted by the war). That is a period that opened with the start of Wittgenstein's lecturing at Cambridge (roughly coincident with his new approach to philosophy), and ending with J. L. Austin's deatha period I am construing as broad enough to capture two other key revolutionary figures, Hilary Putnam and Noam Chomsky. (Stuart Hampshire, in his memoriam, said of Austin, "He could not have adopted a special tone of voice, or attitude of mind, for philosophical questions." That attitude encapsulates the revolution.) A more serious worry for me than those mentioned above is that some of my colleagues may think that the real important revolution in the twentieth century happened somewhat earlier than that. And they would be apt to mention Russell, and Wittgenstein before his change of approach, as at its centre. Now, I agree that those figures were at the centre of an important revolution. I will say a few more words about it later. But, as I see things, that was a nineteenth century revolution-indeed, that century's most important one-begun by Frege in 1879. My twentieth century revolution is, in large part, though not just, a reaction against just the features of this earlier one that most exercised Russell and early Wittgenstein. Some, of course, will find that reaction unfounded. That is a controversy into which I plan to enter in what follows.
Philosophy, 2018
In response to widespread doubts among professional philosophers (Russell, Horwich, Dietrich, McGinn, Chalmers), Stoljar argues for a ‘reasonable optimism’ about progress in philosophy. He defends the large and surprising claim that ‘there is progress on all or reasonably many of the big questions’. However, Stoljar's caveats and admitted avoidance of historical evidence permits overlooking persistent controversies in philosophy of mind and cognitive science that are essentially unchanged since the 17thCentury. Stoljar suggests that his claims are commonplace in philosophy departments and, indeed, the evidence I adduce constitutes an indictment of the widely shared view among professional analytic philosophers.
The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science, 2000
New Challenges to Philosophy of Science, 2013
This chapter looks for issues in scientific disciplines that have received little attention so far in the mainstream philosophy of science (e.g., design sciences, communication sciences, etc.). It addresses new topics in well-stablished disciplines, seeking novelty form different angles of the philosophical research.
This text is an effort to provoke discussion of what everyone will admit is the most important issue of our times but which, ironically, no one is willing to address, namely, Will there be a “Millennium”? And will there be “Philosophy” in the 21st century? I must say that at present I do not have all the answers, but I am open to suggestions and input. With this said, I will proceed. Baynes and McCarthy say in After Philosophy: End or Transformation that all major philosophers today, including Habermas, Rorty, Derrida and Davidson, concede that Philosophy in the traditional sense is over. And thus by doing so they can be said to embrace what Schelling and Hegel, among others, have dubbed “Non-philosophy.” I offer that what this fact really testifies to is none other than the self-elimination of Non-philosophy—and, at the same time, the clearing of the ground for the renaissance and reemergence of True Philosophy, embodied most perfectly in Hegel’s System of Science. It is noteworthy that since the 60s the pace of the Hegel renaissance continues unabated; in the past twenty years more new books and articles on Hegel have been published than on any other major thinker past or present. As a Fordham Ph.D.’s doctoral thesis stated: “when all is said and done, the true measure of progress in Philosophy the last 100 years will be, How far we have gotten in understanding Hegel.”
Contemporary metaphilosophical debates on the future of philosophy invariably include references to the natural sciences. This is wholly understandable given the cognitive and cultural authority of the sciences and their contributions to philosophical thought and practice. However such appeals to the sciences should be moderated by reflections on contingency of sciences. Using the work of contemporary historians and philosophers of science, I argue that an awareness of the radical contingency of science supports the claim that philosophy’s future should not be construed as either dependent or necessarily related to that of the sciences. Therefore contemporary debates – about the possibility of philosophy’s status as a science, say – should be tempered by an appreciation of the fact that science may cease to be a significant feature of future metaphilosophical debates. I conclude by considering the implications of this claim for assessments of the progressiveness of philosophy.
Metascience, 2018
This is a review of a collection of essays on Wittgenstein and scientism: : J. Beale and I. J. Kidd, eds (Routledge, 2017), Wittgenstein and Scientism
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 1991
International Journal of Management Studies and Social Science Research, 2022
The elevation of science and scientific knowledge above other disciplines and knowledge is not without reason or justification. Science has made life easier for people. It has reduced the level of superstition. Above all, it has made the world a global village. However, it has come with its own challenges. In a world dominated by science and technology, can Philosophy, as a discipline, play major roles in the development of a society? How progressive is the society with the rise of philosophy and science? There is no doubt that Philosophy is abstract and largely theoretical. Philosophy is also argumentative and its major tool is argument. Nothing is correct or right unless it is proved. What is however not correct about Philosophy is that it is of no use to non-philosophers and the society in general. As science has its values and usefulness to the society, so also is Philosophy. They may not play the same roles, but their roles are complimentary which eventually leads to the development of the society. Thus, for the success of this work, we shall systematically analyze the successes recorded by scientific growth, the philosophical footprints and influences of these successes and the possibility of a scientific society illumined by philosophical principles.
Studia Gilsoniana, 2014
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.