Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
AI
This paper explores the interplay between human and nonhuman agents in aesthetic experiences, drawing on influences from composers like Morton Feldman. It argues that aesthetic practice is a mutual affecting of various components, raising questions about the nature of materiality and presence in art. Through analysis, the work considers contemporary dance and philosophical concepts, positing that aesthetic judgments are indefinitely interpretable and highlight an inherent incompleteness in art.
MusMat: Brazilian Journal of Music and Mathematics, 2020
Morton Feldman’s Last Pieces for piano solo of 1959 poses an interesting interpretive problem for the performer. As in many Feldman compositions of the 1950s and 60s, the first movement of the work is notated as a series of "sound events" to be played by the performer choosing the durations for each event. The only tempo indications are "Slow. Soft. Durations are free." This situation is complicated by Feldman’s remark about a similar work from 1960, "[I chose] intervals that seemed to erase or cancel out each sound as soon as we hear the next." I interpret this intension to keep the piece fresh and appealing from sound to sound. So, how the pianist supposed to play Last Pieces in order to supplement the composers desire for a sound to "cancel out" preceding sounds? To answer this question, I propose a way of assessing the salience of each sound event in the first movement of Last Pieces, using various means of associating each of its 43 sound...
Mitteilungen der Paul Sacher Stiftung, 2019
2005
Morton Feldman was a self-described “well educated autodidact” composer, an avid collector of modern art and sometimes critic of the visual arts (he contributed to Art News and Art in America and also wrote essays for exhibition catalogues) . His approach to composing was deeply influenced by his associations with the avant-garde of American visual artists in the 1950s. The elimination of symbolism, the simplification of gesture, the avoidance of marked contrasts found even in the earliest iterations of Feldman’s music, owe much to the Abstract Expressionists and more specifically the Color Field artists. By adopting procedures particular to the Abstract Expressionists, he approached the composition of music as those visual artists might have approached painting a canvas. He was in many ways more akin to his peers in the visual art world than he was in to his contemporaries in the music world. Though his lifelong friendship with composer and philosopher of the arts - John Cage was a defining relationship for him, it can be argued that Feldman was more directly preoccupied with the artistic problems that his friends Philip Guston and Mark Rothko were intrigued by, than the musical problems his associate composers were.
Programme notes for concerts, Sheffield Mappin Art Gallery, 2002
Research in Phenomenology, 2013
The present article discusses the relation between painting and music in the work by Paul Klee, bringing it into conversation with the music by Anton Webern. It assumes, as a starting point, that the main question is not about relating painting and music but rather about the relation between moving towards painting and moving towards music, hence the relation between forming forces and not between formed forms. Since for Klee the musical structure of the pictorial is understood as "active linear polyphony," the article develops this notion in conversation with Webern's thoughts on the polyphonic structure of twelve-tone music. The general purpose of the article is to determine what kind of thoughts emerge from the in-between of painting and music.
Introduction The paradigm of research allows us to approach a common discourse at gatherings such as this conference. The effects of the music-making energy that motivates us appear on a continuum from pure sound to abstract questions. Each musical decision produces at least dozen such lines of enquiry, and one reason we gather together is that our particular means of production brings to the surface technical questions that demand technical answers. In this paper I shall look at some technical issues – musical, aesthetic, computational – but my real point is broader and more presumptuous. The various practices of improvising with technology have grown up defining themselves against existing cultural structures; they are not the production of scores, they are not jazz, they challenge mechanical reproduction, take their electroacoustic care over every sample and are then willing to do violence to it should musical truth demand, they argue with ownership, they even try to escape from music into other media or modes of performance at every opportunity. The real badge is of course to have a piece of custom performance kit – generally unreproduced if not unreproducible (a generalisation, but the image is not uncommon). The main point is that the mode of performance tends not to afford participation in a particular practice; it is overtly individualised. I caricature, but there is a degree of self-caricaturing in the practice. I hope to show that rather than being in any way alternative, such a mode of music-making represents a central paradigm of musical activity and understanding. This paper will therefore suggest: • That the interactive improvised work might be acknowledged as a central cultural paradigm – but to do that we need to understand what kind of thing it might be • That to do that we need to sophisticate our understanding of how such activity is distributed through time and space • That in particular we need to see where knowledge arises and how we recognise it • That because technology requires us to be explicit, we need to consider the mechanisms for self-knowledge Definitions What music is at issue here? Lets start by spreading the net too wide: technological not as in plugged-in, amplified or processed but as in a sound surface made possible by technology – and it is only just too far to think of the phonographic listening of Mahler or the additive orchestration of Ravel. Here we're talking about technology that transforms time and memory, causality, the scope of physical and imaginative intentionality. Improvised not as in the arbitrary, the mechanistic or the therapeutic – but in the meaningful determining of the direction of a musical argument during performance. Interactive is the not unproblematic term often used. What kind of work are we dealing with? These questions relate to properties common to all musical 'texts', from Guido to Miles or Karlheinz: the mode, locus and moment of inscription. What modes of inscription are proper to our historical situation? (Score-following, for example, may well turn out to be a non-problem of transition.) How then can we characterise works that characterise themselves by their lack of definition on one hand and individuality on the other? Models for the work – locus and moment Works for performance can be 'thick' or 'thin' in their constitutive properties. If it is thick, the work's determinative properties are comparatively few in number and most of the qualities of a performance are aspects of the performer's interpretation, not of the work as such. The thinner they are, the thinner is the performer to control aspects of the performance. … if the work is thick, a great many of the properties heard in a performance are crucial to its identity and must be reproduced in a fully faithful rendition of the work. The thicker the work, the more the composer controls the sonic detail of its accurate instances. (Davies 2001, 20) Now of course deriving a default model of composition from the status of the nineteenth century score is like understanding architecture on the basis of the pyramids. Tape music offered an alternative pyramid, one that can be erected by one man – an inflatable. But to extend a human-geographical metaphor they cast a long shadow, and it may be us, the peasants trying to work out a means for survival in the noisy musical third world suburbs that can offer an alternative – but to be culturally useful it needs to understand itself better. Recently working on a survey chapter on the psychology of composition I continuously assumed I was missing something – in fact there's precious little of relevance. Sloboda (1985, 118) proposes a model of the process which has validity but looks something like an optimisation algorithm for the solution of a creative problem using available technical means. What is interesting is the way it passes in and out of consciousness. We might define this process thus: Composition is a reflexive, iterative process of inscription. The work, once identified as such and externalisable to some degree, passes circularly between inner and outer states. It passes through internal and external representations – mostly
EXCESS. FORUM FOR PHILOSOPHY AND ART (4.-7.8.2016) 48th International Summer Course for New Music Darmstadt Jörn Peter Hiekel, Dieter Mersch, Michael Rebhahn and Fahim Amir (CURATORS) This forum, consisting of an opening, a closing discussion and three panels, seeks to probe the current state of the relationship between music and philosophy, as well as the mutual consonances and dissonances. With a view to the present, it is of particular interest to ask what questions are stimulating New Music today, what challenges it faces, and what shared themes or »contemporaneities« unite and separate philosophy and New Music today. In this way — and very much following on from earlier discussions in Darmstadt — the forum will attempt to show how compositional strategies and concepts exemplify reflections on changes within the whole of contemporary culture. The forum, which will take place in two languages (German and English, with simultaneous interpretation), defines itself as an open-ended discussion whose topics will be introduced in keynote speeches. In each case, one composer and one philosopher will act as hosts and play the part of structuring and further developing, with their guests, the discussion that already started before the course. PANEL 1: SURPLUS Dieter Mersch ChristianGrüny, Jennifer Walshe, Ashley Fure, Claus-Steffen Mahnkopf, Michael Pisaro, Bernhard Waldenfels The term»surplus, «which is also implied in the over- all title EXCESS, allues to today’s increasing expansion of the compositional through approaches like intermediality, heterogeneity of material, body/performance, theatricality, etc. Thus the term »surplus« relates on the one hand to the »derestriction« of the arts towards different forms of expression, representation and production; but, on the other hand, also to a political aspect between the critique of art as a productive force in modern capitalism and the surplus of the aesthetic as something that does not submit to the cycles of economic exploitation. PANEL 2: THE POLITICAL Michael Rebhahn Douglas Barrett, Dror Feiler, Fahim Amir, Chaya Czernowin, Harry Lehmann, Mathias Spahlinger The political dimension touched on in the first group of themes will be explicitly foregrounded in the second complex. It addresses the ever pressing question of the relationship between art, reality and politics, which constantly arises in new ways for music too. Just as the »worldrelation« of music is being intensely debated at the moment, the concern is at once a far more fundamental analysis of the relationship be- tween the aesthetic and all that characterizes and constitutes the polis, the political and lastly the »community«. What is the role of art in this, especially if the practice of art identifies itself first and foremost as critique, as an element of resistance or subversion against claims to political power? A substantial element of this fundamental problem also encompasses the interplay between music and the historical, as expressed in notions of »contemporaneity« and »witness.« Intervention: Fahim Amir and Tomás Saraceno Every work of art is an uncommitted crime After the critique of Eurocentrism new approaches demand to also »provincialise the human«. If dogs are indeed the new feminists as Carolyn Christov-Bakargiev, curator of dOCUMENTA (13), famously stated in relation to the seminal work of Donna Haraway, what is there to be done in the realms of aesthetics, production and politics? Philosopher Fahim Amir and artist Tomás Saraceno engage in a conversation about challenges and promises of multi species constellations in art starting from both Saracenos work with spiders and Haraways Companion Species Manifesto (2003). A Cyrtophora citricola spider will join the conversation as guest speaker. PANEL 3: MUSIC AS PHILOSOPHY Jörn Peter Hiekel, Simone Mahrenholz, ManosTsangaris, Brian Ferneyhough, Patrick Frank, Gunnar Hindrichs, Albrecht Wellmer Music, like art in general, constitutes its own form of thought and insight that is every bit as advanced as philosophy, but uses other means and follows different »logics.« It is not only a matter of initiating a dialogue between music and philosophy in order to evoke mutual tensions or proximities, but rather of showing how music, or the musical and »compositional,« can be viewed as »a form of philosophy« — and of attributing to it an »epistemic« power of its own. On the one hand, this raises such time-honored questions as that of »truth« in art, which after Hegel was taken up most significantly by Heidegger and Adorno; and on the other hand, it needs to be readjusted to the present conditions. One must therefore interrogate the »self-will« of aesthetic thought and ask what music — especially New Music, as the most »abstract« and at once the most emotional art — »knows,« or how it organizes and reveals its knowledge.
Musical Gesture and Phenomenology of Musical Space in 20th-Century Avant-Garde Music, 2020
In the present paper I propose a conceptual framework that establishes a link between two fundamental concepts of music theory: musical gesture and musical space. The unfolding in time is a fundamental feature of musical gesture. However, in plastic arts, the gesture can only be represented in a spatial form. Since music possesses its own internal space, it is logical to assume that musical space can also carry spatialized gestural "imprints". To describe such indirect manifestations of gesture, I introduce the concept of spatial imprint of musical gesture (SIMG). This concept entails a phenomenological approach to musical space, accordingly to which, the phenomenon of musical space includes all forms of quasi-spatial mental representations of music itself, and excludes all abstract representations like "pitch space", "space" of parameter values, schemes of formal structure, etc. I single out five general aspects of the musical space phenomenon: • Quasi-geometric space: a mental representation of music, based on the analytical spatial vision of its elements (sounds, layers, figures, shapes, etc.). • Space as sound substance: an association of sound with color, light, material, physical properties of substances, etc. • Energetic space: a quasi-spatial representation of forces acting within the musical process. • Synthetic large-scale temporal space. • Physical space. These types of spatial representations generally coexist, but one of them may acquire a leading role in certain styles. The development of the art music during past century placed a priority on three components: quasi-geometrical space, space as substance, and physical space. Quoting works by Schönberg, Webern, Stockhausen, Xenakis, and Ligeti, I consider some paradigmatic examples, in which the SIMG becomes a key element from technical and aesthetic standpoints. In the last part of the paper I present a hypothesis, according to which, the process of "spatialization" of music and "migration" of gesture to musical space could be a result of cultural trauma. This trauma consists of the distrust of human communion and cathartic consolation through direct empathy, or, more broadly, in a distrust of Humanism.
This paper outlines a new basic model of extrinsic significance in music. Simply, a map of how things 'about' or 'from' the world can make their way into pieces of music. It will be founded on the somewhat artificial distinction between two forms of musical reality: 1. Musical experience that exists “without concept, object, purpose” (Dahlhaus, 1991) that is music that is self-referential; that rejects analysis that is based in any way on the external world. 2. Musical experience that exists as a result of it's relationship with reality. Although both of these realities are in operation in every piece of music, the research is particularly concerned with the second definition, which is often given misnomers like “conceptual”, “programmatic” or “extra-musical”. In the paper, it will be stressed that no musical experience ever be dismissed under a term such as “extra-musical”. I will talk about my own work as a composer dealing with referentiality, mimetic behaviour, the movement of thought, self-awareness, irony, critique and many other challenging, world-relating things. I will give many examples of existing music, selected from across history and culture for how clearly they contain a particular worldly trait. For this reason, I hope that the research feels most like a piece of cartography for navigating your way through the world with music, and for navigating your way through music with the world. After describing how things about the world make their way into music, I will briefly offer collected observations and my own personal experiences as to why this might happen in the composer's process. This will be to talk of inspiration as much as technique. I will talk about how my compositional process has become more aware of these pathways, and eventually included their use as part of a new understanding of the material of music.
2009
Style, “Arts Magazine”, December 1983, pp. 94-100, and Mark Tobey: City Paintings, National Gallery of Art, Washington 1984 (with an essay by E. Rathbone). 3. Cf. Irving SANDLER, “The Club”, in Abstract Expressionism. A Critical Record, ed. by David Shapiro and Cecile Shapiro, Cambridge/New York, Cambridge University Press 1990, p. 54. One of the texts, Lecture on Nothing, was published in John Cage, Silence, Hanover New Hampshire, Wesleyan University Press 1973, pp. 109-128 4. Cf. Steven JOHNSON, Rothko Chapel and Rothko's Chapel, “Perspectives of New Music”, XXXII/2 1994, pp. 6-53. 5. Morton FELDMAN, "Between Categories", in Give My Regard to Eighth Street: Collected Writings of Morton Feldman edited by B. H. Friedman, Cambridge MA, Exact Change, 2000, pp. 83-89. 6. Ibid., p. 88. 7. M. FELDMAN, “After Modernism”, in ibid., pp. 67-79: 78. 8. Stefan WOLPE, On New (and Not-So-New) Music in America, translated by Austin Clarkson, “Journal of Music Theory”, XXVIII/1 1984,...
In an essay titled “Coping with pianos”, Alfred Brendel assures us that “anyone who has ever traveled with a piano knows that the same instrument not only sounds different in different halls, it even seems to feel different in its mechanism…” Even more strikingly, this difference in the feel of the instrument manifests itself in the same space and on the same day between the afternoon rehearsal and the evening performance. On Brendel’s account, the acoustic difference the presence of an audience makes figures into the performance experience of the pianist in significant ways, impacting even the experience of an intimately familiar instrument. The present research focuses on the role of listening in acts of performance, aiming to open to investigation the ways that pianists may adjust their actions in performance in order to obtain a desired sort of sound under particular acoustic circumstances. It further aims to complicate the idea of timbre in piano performance, seeking to move away from a conception of timbre as an aspect of sound given solely by the instrument, and move towards a conception of timbre as a given range of possibilities available to the pianist.
Resonant Structures, 2016
Introduction, Background, or, How We Arrived Here To work with an ontology of music is to be engaged in a perpetually renewing object and perspectives. Traditionally, music has been regarded as the organization of sound, and implied in this is an organizing subject. We might identify this subject as a performer or composer or producer or any number of cultural roles, but what remains across all of these distinctions is the act of fixing relations between objects so as to create a specific experiential circumstance. Its objects can consist of pitches, melodies, rhythms, and harmonies, but more broadly any events, processes, and concepts recognized ontologically as a single entity. Fixing relations also includes setting them in a state of possibility as opposed to actuality: rather than a musical event happening or not happening, it may happen depending on the immediate circumstances of performance. Referred to as indeterminate, chance, or aleatoric music, this practice opened up inscription and performance into a continuum 1 of potential music, one of the many paradigm shifts that altered art and aesthetics in the twentieth century. Composer Michael Pisaro describes these shifts as "truth procedures," in which a founding event makes recognizable a site of conceptual rupture from which subjects pursue the rupture's widest consequences and implications. 2 Among the truth procedures he recognizes is one he calls the "experimental" in which the musical is no longer necessarily contingent upon a knowable outcome. If any singular piece of music did the most to break down music into this 1 With reference to Adam Harper's conception of musical variables. This idea will return as a system of mapping qualitative points of musical practice.
2017
This portfolio of work explores alternative methods of musical composition that question the distinction between composer and performer, presenting an integrated and interdisciplinary artistic approach that aims to engage a broader public in the production of experimental music. The seventeen pieces in the portfolio are playful outcomes of a practice that, whilst rooted in musical concerns, does not privilege the sounding result. In the accompanying commentary the heritage of experimental music and Fluxus is used as a starting point to reconsider the traditionally separate roles of composer and performer. I assert that these roles currently remain distinct and separate in contemporary practice, despite the challenge that experimental music and Fluxus posed to conventional music-making. In order to address this I reconfigure the relationships between composer, performer and listener through an interpretation of a diagram by experimental composer George Brecht, and develop a framework in which the act of composition can be performed through ‘reading’, ‘character’ and ‘playing’.
M/C Journal, 2016
Interactive improvisational musical spaces (which is to say, nearly all musical spaces) involve affective relations among bodies: between the bodies of human performers, between performers and active listeners, between the sonic "bodies" that comprise the multiple overlapping events that constitute a musical performance's unfolding. Music scholarship tends to focus on either music's sonic materialities (the sensible; what can be heard) or the cultural resonances that locate in and through music (the political or hermeneutic; how meaning is inscribed in and for a listening subject).
2021
What does a one hour contemporary orchestral piece by Georg Friedrich Haas have in common with a series of glitch-noise electronic tracks by Pan Sonic? This book proposes that, despite their differences, they share a particular understanding of sound that is found across several quite distinct genres of contemporary art music: the ecstatic-materialist perspective. Sound in the ecstatic-materialist perspective is considered as a material mass or element, unfolding in time, encountered by a listener, for whom the experience of that sound exceeds the purely sonic without becoming entirely divorced from its materiality. It is "material" by virtue of the focus on the texture, consistency, and density of sound; it is "ecstatic" in the etymological sense, that is to say that the experience of this sound involves an instability; an inclination to depart from material appearance, an ephemeral and transitory impulse in the very perception of sound to something beyond-but still related to-it. By examining musical pieces from spectralism to electroacoustic domains, from minimalism to glitch electronica and dubstep, this book identifies the key intrinsic characteristics of this musical perspective. To fully account for this perspective on sonic experience, listener feedback and interviews with composers and performers are also incorporated. Sound in the ecstatic-materialist perspective is the common territory where composers, sound artists, performers, and listeners converge.
Aesthetics, 2012
Steve Reich (1936- ), in his essay “Music as a Gradual Process” (1968), wrote that “a compositional process and a sounding music [...] are one and the same thing.” His aesthetic creed of “perceptible processes,” indicated in these words, is known as the basic idea of minimal music. Although minimal music has been considered a counterpart of minimal art, this essay first appeared in the exhibition catalogue of Anti-Illusion: Procedures/Materials (Whitney Museum of American Art, 1969), an exhibition recognized as a threshold of postminimalism in the plastic arts. In this paper, I would like to clarify a linkage between Reich’s music and postminimal art in view of his involvement in the Anti-Illusion show. The theme of the Anti-Illusion show was to refocus on the process of making art. By emphasizing the processes and materials of the works, the participating artists tried to deny illusion and expose the reality of art. Among these works, Reich performed his Pendulum Music, in which he made the sounding process visible as microphones’ swinging. This piece clearly demonstrates that Reich’s claim in “Music as a Gradual Process” was propounded in connection with postminimal art as an attempt to disclose musical processes and thereby reveal the real.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.