Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
Most of my papers fall into four related areas. Below I provide a brief description of my work in each area, followed by abstracts of some of my main papers in that area. (Some papers fall into two areas.) The abstracts explain how the papers interrelate, and how together they develop a cohesive argument for a unique non-reductive view of conscious experience.
For the last few decades, consciousness has been in the forefront of neuroscience as well as in the forefront of religious doctrines for further investigation. Indeed it is a vast subject, thus more specifically, what I will investigate and convey in this essay is the interdisciplinary correlatives between the scientific perspectives and that of Buddhist teachings. In regards to science, I will include neuroscientific perspectives without this constricting this essay to include other point of views that originate in different disciplines but nevertheless integrate well with science, such as psychological and philosophical perspectives. In regards to the Buddhist doctrine I will refer to fundamental principles of emptiness (Suññata) and dependent co-arising (paticcasamuppāda) to exemplify notions of experience related to consciousness. Passing through these contradictory disciplines in the past but cooperative at present, and taking in account important philosophies of science and Buddhism to explore “consciousness” in its broad and complex view, I will offer a perspective on what can be reasoned as ‘essence consciousness’ and 'Information Data'.
Philosophical Topics, 1989
One of the most amazing things about the past half century or so in analytic philosophy of mind is the scarcity of serious work on the nature of consciousness. Even works purportedly about consciousness have very little to say about the general structure of consciousness or about its special features. Thus for example of three recent books containing "Consciousness"t in their titles not one contains even an attempt to state a comprehensive account of the structure of conscious states, much less state a general theory that will account for subjectivity, the stream of consciousness, the qualitative character of conscious states, etc. In each case consciousness is regarded not as a primary subject matter in the philosophy of mind but as a "problem", a potential embarrassment to the author's theory, which is,
Introduction: Presentation and the Structure of the World 1
Prolegomena, 2016
In his book The Significance of Consciousness, Charles Siewert argues that some of our phenomenal features are intentional features, because we are assessable for accuracy in virtue of having these phenomenal features. In this paper, I will, first, show that this argument stands in need of disambiguation, and will emerge as problematic on both available readings. Second, I will use Thomas Szanto’s recent ideas to develop a deeper understanding of the difficulties with Siewert’s argument. Szanto emphatically contrasts the Husserlian, constitutive conception of intentionality with the mainstream, representational conception. If we interpret Siewert’s ideas in representational terms, it will be possible to add to my critical objections. However, I will suggest that it is also possible to interpret, or perhaps to modify, Siewert’s views in Husserlian constitutive terms, thereby addressing the objections raised in the present paper.
I discuss three issues about the relation of phenomenal consciousness, in the sense Siewert isolates, to intentionality. The first is whether, contrary to Siewert, phenomenal consciousness requires higher-order representation. The second is whether intentional features of conscious states are identical with phenomenal features, as Siewert argues, or merely conceptually supervene on them, with special attention to cross modal representations of objects in space. The third is whether phenomenal features are identical with what we can have first person access to, with special attention to features of thoughts that are individuated by reference to the self and the present time.
Philosophical perspectives, 2007
ALEFTP 7501 Approaches to Consciousness: Introductory Materials, 2021
Introductory essay and glossary for the Alef Trust 7501 Approaches to Consciousness course. Updated for August 2024.
The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness
Philosophers traditionally recognize two main features of mental states: intentionality and phenomenal consciousness. To a first approximation, intentionality is the aboutness of mental states, and phenomenal consciousness is the felt, experiential, qualitative, or "what it's like" aspect of mental states. In the past few decades, these features have been widely assumed to be distinct and independent. But several philosophers have recently challenged this assumption, arguing that intentionality and consciousness are importantly related. This article overviews the key views on the relationship between consciousness and intentionality and describes our favored view, which is a version of the phenomenal intentionality theory, roughly the view that the most fundamental kind of intentionality arises from phenomenal consciousness.
A conceptual framework for demystifying consciousness from a physicalist perspective. Attempting to address the "hard problem" of subjective experience.
Karl Jaspers Forum, Target Article 2, 17 July 1997. Online journal
[1] ABSTRACT: The Science of Consciousness (SOC) is continuous with everyday thinking and with other scientific specialities in beginning inevitably with the inquiring subject's own conscious experiencing. This does not lead to solipsism, because the hypothesis of an independently existing world is the best hypothesis to explain the facts of subjective experience. SOC is unique among all ways of knowing in needing to be fully critical, not simply as academic philosophy is by conceptualizing the structure of conscious inquiry, but by being reflectively aware of consciousness as such, the womb from which inquiry is born. Therefore, in SOC the scientist and the philosopher merge. Initially, this reflective awareness means being open to experiencing non-naturalistic as well as naturalistic claims, altered states of consciousness as well as ordinary ones. It is an empirical issue, not to be decided a priori by some empiricist commitment, whether such non-naturalistic claims and altered states actually exist and what their relevance is to understanding consciousness
Perceptual Experience is a significant book. Among its fifteen papers are some likely to be widely cited in future. The central theme is the following epistemological question - what is experience, that it should enable us to know the world? As the editors emphasize in their introduction, philosophical discussion of this question was dominated, for most of the last century, by the arguments from hallucina- tion and illusion.
Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion Volume 3, 2011
The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, 2007
This is a prepublication version of the final chapter from the Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. In it I re-examine the basic conditions required for a study of conscious experiences in the light of progress made in recent years in the field of consciousness studies. I argue that neither dualist nor reductionist assumptions about subjectivity versus objectivity and the privacy of experience versus the public nature of scientific observations allow an adequate understanding of how studies of consciousness actually proceed. The chapter examines the sense in which the experimenter is also a subject, the sense in which all experienced phenomena are private and subjective, the different senses in which a phenomenon can nevertheless be public and observations of it objective, and the conditions for intra-subjective and intersubjective repeatability. The chapter goes on to re-examine the empirical method and how methods used in psychology differ from those used in physics. I argue that a reflexive understanding of these relationships supports a form of “critical phenomenology” that fits consciousness studies smoothly into science.
Abstract. This essay is a survey of the field of consciousness studies, its history, scope, and a little about its future. It’s principal focus is on Western thinking about consciousness beginning in classical times and continuing down to the present. It highlights and briefly describes major streams of thought including ideas from ancient Greece, German Idealism, British Empiricism, 20 th century European phenomenology, and important contemporary areas of research and scholarship. These include American pragmatism, developmental psychology, transpersonalism, analytic philosophy, computationalism, neural networks, and physics. The essay also briefly explores possible future trends in the study of consciousness. Keywords: consciousness, American pragmatism, developmental psychology, transpersonalism, analytic philosophy, computationalism, neural networks, physics
Current Perspectives on a Science of Consciousness, 2009
Acta Psychologica, 1994
2011
In response to Petitmengin and Bitbol's recent account of first-person methodologies in the study of consciousness, I provide a revised model of our introspective knowledge of our own conscious experience. This model, which I call the existential constitution model of phenomenal knowledge, avoids the problems that Petitmengin and Bitbol identify with standard observational models of introspection while also avoiding an underlying metaphorical misconception in their own proximity model, which misconstrues first-person knowledge of consciousness in terms of a dichotomous epistemic relationship. The end result is a clearer understanding of the unique nature and epistemic properties of our knowledge of consciousness, as well as the epistemic status of subsequent first-person reports on conscious experience .
Cognition, 2001
Most 'theories of consciousness' are based on vague speculations about the properties of conscious experience. We aim to provide a more solid basis for a science of consciousness. We argue that a theory of consciousness should provide an account of the very processes that allow us to acquire and use information about our own mental states -the processes underlying introspection. This can be achieved through the construction of information processing models that can account for 'Type-C' processes. Type-C processes can be specified experimentally by identifying paradigms in which awareness of the stimulus is necessary for an intentional action. The Shallice (1988b) framework is put forward as providing an initial account of Type-C processes, which can relate perceptual consciousness to consciously performed actions. Further, we suggest that this framework may be refined through the investigation of the functions of prefrontal cortex. The formulation of our approach requires us to consider fundamental conceptual and methodological issues associated with consciousness. The most significant of these issues concerns the scientific use of introspective evidence. We outline and justify a conservative methodological approach to the use of introspective evidence, with attention to the difficulties historically associated with its use in psychology.
This thesis aims at laying the groundwork for a research program in philosophy of mind by arguing for two theoretical positions, internalism and representationalism (intentionalism), which are rarely defended jointly, but which together can form the basis for a plausible theory of the mind. The first chapter argues for internalism against the dominant externalist view. Firstly, it is discussed what the best way is to elucidate the debate between internalism and externalism rooted in the Twin Earth thought experiment. (Putnam 1975) It is argued that the issue between internalists and externalists is whether concrete items that stand in a referential relation to mental states are among the constitutive bases of mental states. The Dry Earth thought experiment (Boghossian 1998) is introduced to make a case for internalism, relying on concepts that do not refer. Externalist counter-arguments are introduced and rejected. The second chapter argues for representationalism/intentionalism against qualia theory. It is argued that there are no mental qualities (qualia) that account for the qualitative aspects of phenomenology. What do account for the qualitative aspects of phenomenology are apparent qualities of the intentional objects of conscious experiences, the qualities the world is represented as having by the experiences. Three sets of arguments for qualia are introduced and rejected. The first set of arguments are the type of arguments that are variants of the argument from error, which are rejected by an intentionalist analysis of mentality, and an epistemology of experience is developed where experience provides an acquaintance relation between a subject and something abstract such as a possibility. This makes it unnecessary to postulate epistemic relations both to concretely instantiated items in the environment and to mental items such as qualia or sense-data. Arguments based on allegedly non-representational states such as double vision and afterimages are shown to fail by demonstrating that such states are non-endorsed representations. Arguments that rely on spectrum inversion cases where representational content allegedly differs while qualitative phenomenology stays the same are rejected by arguing against the account of representation that underlies such arguments. (The order of the two chapters is largely arbitrary, though a rejection of externalism is useful in arguing against the argument from spectrum inversion.) The account is completed by briefly discussing and rejecting the disjunctivist theory of perception, and some other motivations for externalism such as externalism’s advantage in providing a naturalistic account of mentality is discussed. The thesis concludes by pointing at the naturalistic prospects for an account of mentality that analyses mental states as representational states while the representational content is based neither on mental qualities like qualia, nor on causal-informational relations to environmental items. I further speculate about the role of powers and dispositions of organisms that might underpin a future naturalistic analysis of mentality, and also consider the plausibility of a mysterian account of mind where the special mystery regarding the explanatory gap about consciousness is downgraded by suggesting that explanatory gaps might be widespread in nature, such as in our failure to logically link qualities like color and sound as we experience them to the lower-level physical phenomena they supervene on.