Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
Chomsky thinks that Plato's problem is especially visible in language. Plato's problem -which is also called by him "Russell's Problem" -is "how can we know so much when the evidence for what we know is so vanishingly small". Plato's problem is brought out in the dialogue Meno. This is also called the Poverty of Stimulus or the Poverty of Evidence problem. The problem is that it is clear that we have certain kinds of knowledge, but it is not clear how we came by this knowledge. Plato thought that the solution was that we recollected the knowledge from the time the soul saw the Forms (the theory of Anamnesis, or Recollection).
Serious Philosophy
Considering Chomsky's claim that language can only have happened in the human species by means of a one time mutation in one individual which provided that individual and its descendants the capacity for inner thought which non-carriers of the relevant gene lacked. On this view language springs from thought (thinking capacity) rather than serving to foster it by providing a medium for its occurrence.
Fuel and Energy Abstracts, 2006
This volume is the latest in a series called Philosophers and their Critics, published by Blackwell, with the self-articulated purpose of "reconstruct [ing] [the] vital interplay among thinkers", and consisting of "a temporary assessment of an important living philosopher's work, [a] collection of essays written by an interdisciplinary group of critics addressing the substantial theses of the philosopher's corpus, [and responses from the philosopher] to his or her critics, clarif[ying] crucial points of the discussion, or updat[ing] his or her doctrines" (inside cover). As such, it should come as no great surprise that the articles in this publication really are, for the most part, substantially more philosophically grounded, than they are linguistically. Whilst all issues covered are of interest and relevance to the linguistically-minded reader, the style of discourse through which one must wade is decidedly less concise than those of us with a quasi-scientific bent are generally used to. In fact, I myself breathed an audible sigh of relief on reaching the sixth of the ten articles in this compilation, since it is at this half-way mark that the focus changes noticeably from the more philosophical issues of the mind-body problem, materialism, and mental representation, to the more linguistic issues of semantics, referentiality, innateness, and I-versus E-language. Nevertheless, my struggles with the first half were well worth it, as I feel I learnt a lot, and have now acquired a clearer and more comprehensive view of where Chomsky's argumentation as a whole stems from.
The Analysis of Verbal Behavior, 2007
Chomsky's (1959) review of Skinner's (1957)Verbal Behavior has been influential and attributed with a role in the cognitive revolution. However, while counter reviews from within behavior analysis have noted that Chomsky misunderstood the subject matter, certain aspects of his scholarship have been underdiscussed. This includes several instances where Chomsky misquotes Skinner or takes his quotes out of context. Similar to the findings of Sokal (1996a, 1996b), it is speculated that the problems with Chomsky were overlooked by cognitive psychologists because his general outlook was accepted. Implications for the editorial review process are discussed.
The Analysis of Verbal Behavior, 2000
In 1957 Noam Chomsky published Syntactic Structures, expressing views characterized as constituting a "revolution" in linguistics. Chomsky proposed that the proper subject matter of linguistics is not the utterances of speakers, but what speakers and listeners know. To that end, he theorized that what they know is a system of rules that underlie actual performance. This theory became known as transformational grammar. In subsequent versions of this theory, rules continued to play a dominant role. However, in 1980 Chomsky began a second revolution by proposing the elimination of rules in a new theory: the principles-and-parameters approach. Subsequent writings finalized the abandonment of rules. Given the centrality of rules to cognitivism, this paper argues that Chomsky's second revolution constitutes a departure from cognitivism. "In Woody Allen's story 'The Whore of Mensa,' the patron asks, 'Suppose I wanted Noam Chomsky explained to me by two girls?' 'It'd cost you,' she replies" (Pinker, 1994, p. 126; see Allen, 1972, pp. 32-38). Noam Chomsky's linguistics career spans half a century. The scholarly product of that career-papers, books, lectures-has been prodigious. Reviewing enough of this material to develop an easy familiarity with its central themes is a daunting task. Further, Chomsky's work is replete with formalisms and other technical expressions, making much of it unfathomable to those outside the field of linguistics. Because his views have changed frequently over time, any account of Chomskyan linguistics must carefully specify which works by Chomsky are being used as source material. And Chomsky's apparent penchant for historical revisionism-reinterpreting his past statements in a self-serving manner that often strains credulity (e.g., see Matthews, 1993, pp. 191-192)makes it even more difficult to get a
International Philosophical Quarterly
This article explores the tension between the antithetical philosophies of empiricism and innatism underlying Chomskyan linguistics. It first follows the trail of empiricism in North American linguistics, starting from the work of Leonard Bloomfield at the beginning of the Twentieth century, and its influence on the Chomskyan paradigm, after which the Kantian trail of innatism initiated by Chomsky himself is reconnoitered. It is argued that the Chomskyan approach to natural language represents a paradigmatic example of the unsavory consequences of the divorce between mind and matter instituted by Kant, in particular because human language involves an intimate relation between both types of reality. In Chomsky's Generative Grammar, on the other hand, the material side of language is treated as completely autonomous from its mental correlate and analyzed in terms of a priori conceptual structures and computational operations; for its part, the mental side of language is treated as innate; the relation between the two is thus made utterly obscure and incomprehensible. The conclusion of the article argues in favour of a more balanced approach inspired by Aristotelianism and Paul Ricoeur's hermeneutics.
1 this contribution contains the faithful transcript of chomsky's seminar. the notes provide some additional references. although the contribution has been organized and revised by all authors, V. Bambini is responsible for questions 1-2, 8-11 and for the notes, while c. chesi for questions 3-7. We would like to thank the students who participated to the initiative and submitted their questions, and the collegio ghislieri in Pavia for hosting the seminar.
International Journal of Linguistics and Culture
Cognition, language faculty, Universal Grammar, Principles and Parameters, Transformational Generative Grammar, Phrase Structure Rules, TransformationsThis review seeks to highlight Chomsky’s major contributions to the field of linguistics. He changed linguists’ conception about the nature of language, from an externalized to internalized approach. This shift also resulted in the language being thought of as a cognitive phenomenon rather than as a set of structures to be analyzed for their correctness or incorrectness. He argued that language is internalized, and not learned. His arguments to prove his stance introduced the concept of language faculty, its workings, Universal Grammar, Principles and Parameters, and Transformational and Generative Grammar. The TGG also significantly overhauled the existent phrase structure rules. These rules were brought to follow binarity principles that dictated that a node cannot have less than or more than two branches. Besides, the concept of U...
Avram Noam Chomsky (born in 1928) is an American professor and public intellectual known for his work in linguistics, political activism, and social criticism. Sometimes called "the father of modern linguistics"1, Chomsky is also a major figure in analytic philosophy and one of the founders of the field of cognitive science. In 1959, Noam Chomsky published a scathing review of B. F. Skinner's book Verbal Behavior.[6] At the time, Skinner's behaviorist paradigm dominated the field of psychology within the United States. Most psychologists focused on functional relations between stimulus and response, without positing internal representations. Chomsky argued that in order to explain language, we needed a theory like generative grammar, which not only attributed internal representations but characterized their underlying order.2 Chomsky's special viewpoint was the sentence-section of the parser, which concentrates on the grammars. Another section is the word's section of the parser etymology, which describes the etymology of the words. Both sections of the parser seem to be developed as optimized architectures. The words' architecture is permanently being optimized by degeneration and renewing by metamorphoses of the metaphors. The first concepts of the fundamental words seems to be generated as references to the 5 independent phonetic sources of the human voice: the tongue, the lips, teeth, palatal, and the guttural with the vocal chords. These sources are defined as the Places of articulation. Generative grammar considers grammar as a system of rules that generates exactly those combinations of words that form grammatical sentences in a given language. It is a system of explicit rules that may apply repeatedly to generate an indefinite number of sentences which can be as long as one wants them to be.3 This essay concentrates on the relations between the grammar and the etymology of the fundamental pentagrammatons (father, mother, the virtues and the sky-god), which had been composed from letters, which represent the 5 phonetic sources of the human voice. The Vocabulary of the 5-Letter Words contains ~424 pentagrammatons, from which a number of compositions may purposely represent the fundamental words. Other pentagrammatons may unintentionally represent the 5 phonetic sources of the human voice. The conclusions in this essay on etymology may represent a helpful tool to understand the evolution of our languages.
The author identifies selected implicit or not fully explicit assumptions made by Noam Chomsky in his theory of language. Through careful lecture of Chomsky's work, she aims to expose the solutions this linguist proposes with respect to two fundamental questions: the question of methodology and the question of the ontological status of language. This paper consists of two main parts. In the first one, the author reviews the most central postulates of Chomsky"s methodology and the basic theses regarding language that can be found in his works. In the second part, she turns to the problem question that is mentioned in the title of this paper, that is, the reservations regarding the assumptions underlying his works.
But both are doing their jobs with quite new ideas, digging as profoundly as possible with an equal commitment in philosophy as in politics: enough reasons, it seems to me for us to expect a fascinating debate about philosophy and about politics.
International Philosophical Quarterly 62(4): 383-411, 2022
This article explores the tension between the antithetical philosophies of empiricism and innatism underlying Chomskyan linguistics. It first follows the trail of empiricism in North American linguistics, starting from the work of Leonard Bloomfield at the beginning of the Twentieth century, and its influence on the Chomskyan paradigm, after which the Kantian trail of innatism initiated by Chomsky himself is reconnoitered. It is argued that the Chomskyan approach to natural language represents a paradigmatic example of the unsavory consequences of the divorce between mind and matter instituted by Kant, in particular because human language involves an intimate relation between both types of reality. In Chomsky's Generative Grammar, on the other hand, the material side of language is treated as completely autonomous from its mental correlate and analyzed in terms of a priori conceptual structures and computational operations; for its part, the mental side of language is treated as innate; the relation between the two is thus made utterly obscure and incomprehensible. The conclusion of the article argues in favour of a more balanced approach inspired by Aristotelianism and Paul Ricoeur's hermeneutics.
The paper focuses on the debate as it is dealt with in chapter 4 of Chomsky (1986), where the MIT linguist defends his own view of “knowledge of language”, especially answering some objections by Dummett. In this same chapter Chomsky also discusses some conclusions drawn by Kripke (1982) about the notion of “private language”, following and developing Wittgenstein’s view on the issue: Kripke’s arguments are not directed against Chomsky’s view of language and knowledge of language, but, if they were shown to be tenable, they would undermine the whole theoretical construction of generative grammar, as Chomsky himself (1986: 226) suggests. The paper therefore examines Chomsky’s answers to Kripke and Dummett and tries to give an assessment of the debate. Chomsky’s answers appear as essentially convincing; this does not mean, however, that the issue of what “knowledge of language” is has really found a completely satisfactory answer. This problem is dealt with in the final part of this paper, also referring to some suggestions by a cognitive scientist (Pylyshyn 1980; 1984).
When asked whether the history of his work on linguistics is misconceived, Chomsky (p.c.) replied by saying that '[t]he history of [Generative Grammar] is hopelessly misconceived, sometimes ludicrously so,' and he referred, as an example, to overtly hostile critics such as Boden (2006). 1 However, as the present section purports to show, there seems to be no reason to believe that certified members of the Chomskyan school are immune from historical misconceptions, albeit of a different nature to those displayed by Boden. A case in point is Boeckx and Hornstein's (2004/2010) goal-directed approach to the development of Chomsky's work on linguistic theory. 2
Th is article examines the critique of materialism in the work of Noam Chomsky which treats the doctrine as lacking in any clear content. It is argued that Chomsky's critique is a coherent one drawing on an understanding of the Newtonian revolution in science, on a modular conception of the mind, and on the related conception of epistemic boundedness. Th e article also seeks to demonstrate the limits of Chomsky's position by drawing attention to his use of the third-person point of view in considering the mental and his resulting failure to make good sense of consciousness. Finally, a dual-aspect theory is recommended which would incorporate Chomsky's agnosticism about the nature of matter.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.