Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2023, Journal of Philosophical Theological Research
https://doi.org/10.22091/jptr.2023.9148.2856…
21 pages
1 file
Avicenna has aimed to establisha harmonized philosophical system that incorporates logic, epistemology, metaphysics, natural philosophy, and other types of knowledge. Although he has not directly written anything about the metaphysical foundations of science, we believe that there are some implications in his philosophy that could be considered astruthmakers of scientific propositions. As natural law is significantly correlated to "experiment", we will first discuss the epistemological aspect of experiments in Avicennian philosophy. He believes that the observation of a repeated event could lead us to a causal relationship due to the fact that accidental events are neither permanent nor frequent. Following that, the logical approach which corresponds to this epistemology will be introduced. As Avicenna's logic does not directly consider such an approach, we are to derive it from apparently disconnected chapters and then formulate them. It will be indicated that Avicenna has been aware of the differences between propositions that merely refer to existent instances and ones that consider the nature of instances. The latter obviously could refer to both existent instances and hypothetical instances. Finally, we present some points in his metaphysics that could establisha metaphysical basis for propositions concerning natural law. In addition, we will indicate that Avicenna's system is able to justify the counterfactual conditionals that relate to laws of nature.
Oriens, 2016
The notion of per se (kath'hautó) is a signature component of Aristotle's theory of science. This paper has two aims: (i) to examine for the first time Avicenna's (d. 1037) account of per se (ḏātī) in the context of his theory of demonstration, especially in the Kitāb al-Burhān, and more generally in what I shall call the Posterior Analytics complex, i.e., a larger set of relevant texts from Avicenna's logical works that deal with An. Post., and (ii) to connect it with his theory of predicables as formulated in the Kitāb al-Madḫal, and more generally in what I shall call, by analogy, the Isagoge complex. In the Posterior Analytics complex, Avicenna reasserts the role of per se predication and articulates an innovative and systematic interpretation (showing a debt towards Fārābī and the Greek commentary tradition) of the notions of per se 1 and per se 2 originally developed by Aristotle in An. Post. a4 around the idea of a term being taken in the definition of another term. In the Isagoge complex, Avicenna understands per se 1 and 2 in terms of two types of entailment of different strength—containment (taḍammun) and implication (iltizām)—, which are in turn associated with the technical notions of inseparability in conception (taṣawwur) and in imagination (tawahhum). As a result, the distinction between per se 1 and 2 in Avicenna turns out to be philosophically grounded in a larger theoretical framework than it is in Aristotle. In addition to its intrinsic interest, Avicenna's solution also counts as an interpretive effort that aims to solve some traditional exegetical problems in Aristotle, e.g., the question whether the class of per se 2 predicates from An. Post. a4 and that of per se accidents coincide, an issue that has vexed commentators since antiquity.
PROBLEMS FROM ARMSTRONG, Acta Philosophica Fennica 84, Helsinki 2008. Eds. Tim De Mey and Markku Keinänen.
British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 2015
In his Kitab al-Burhan (Book of Demonstration), Avicenna discusses a theoretical framework broadly inspired by Aristotle's Posterior Analytics which brings together logic, epistemology and metaphysics. One of the central questions explored in the book is the problem of the relation between knowledge, certainty and causal explanation. Burhan 1.8, in particular, is devoted to the analysis of how certainty comes about in causal as opposed to non-causal contexts. The distinction is understood in Avicenna's system as one between cases in which the conclusion of an argument is warranted only in virtue of an appropriate middle term, and cases in which there is no such intermediary because the predicative link between subject and predicate of the conclusion is immediate. In this context, Avicenna makes use of the case of relative terms (muḍ afat) to clarify certain crucial aspects of his theory. The paper explores this discussion and shows how Avicenna's account of the relatively marginal role of relatives in the context of demonstration depends on insights that are central to his metaphysics and epistemology.
Oriens, 2020
The separated intellects play a crucial but notoriously controversial role within the Neoplatonic systems of al-Fārābī and Avicenna. While both thinkers provide an array of proofs to support the existence of such immaterial substances, the most enduring of these is based on a metaphysical rule of Avicenna's metaphysics known as the "rule of one" (qāʿidat al-wāḥid): that from the One, only one proceeds (lā yaṣdur ʿan l-wāḥid illā l-wāḥid). The following paper explores the various ways in which Avicenna defended this principle and traces their reception in the post-classical period, thereby showing how vigorously the question of emanation was debated among scholars of the later medieval period.
International Philosophical Quarterly , 2022
THIS PAPER DISCUSSES AVICENNA’S concept of ambiguity/analogy and argues that while Avicenna doesn’t mention it explicitly there is an analogy of the predication of being between creatures and God, the Necessary of Existence. A consequence of this analogical predication is that for Avicenna, like Aquinas, God does not fall under the subject of metaphysics common being or being qua being.1 If the predication were univocal as some scholars contend such as Timothy Noone and Olga Lizzini,2 then God would fall under the subject of metaphysics, common being as he does according to Ramon Guerrero and John Wippel.3 This paper has three parts. First, it discusses the comparison between Avicenna and Aristotle on pros hen equivocation/analogy. Second, it discusses the texts within Avicenna which suggest an analogical predication and which can reasonably be seen as establishing a transcendental predication between God and creatures. Finally, it develops the consequences of Avicenna’s view for the relationship between God and the subject of metaphysics common being or being qua being and argues that God does not fall under common being.
Journal of the History of Philosophy, 2015
There has been a long-held misconception among historians of philosophy and science that apart from brief comments in Aristotle and Averroes, the theory of minima naturalia had to await Latin Schoolmen for its full articulation. Recently scholars have shown that far from sporadic comments on minima naturalia, Averroes in fact had a fully developed and well-integrated theory of them. in this study, i complement these scholars' important work by considering Avicenna's place in the history and development of the doctrine of the minima naturalia. There is no study to date that mentions Avicenna in connection with this doctrine despite the fact that he dedicated an entire chapter to it in his Physics, yet Avicenna's account is at least as developed as and even better integrated than Averroes's presentation. The present study situates Avicenna's position within the more general history of atomism, and introduces Avicenna's "new argument" for natural minima. The argument is important not only for its novelty but also because it shows how Avicenna integrated Aristotle's account of minima naturalia into a theory of mixture as well.
The Logic of Avicenna from the Viewpoint of Nicholas Rescher, 2023
Avicenna is the most influential logician in the Arabic tradition. Logic for Avicenna is said to be what “prevents the mind from errors”. Although his work can be traced back to the ancient logic (Aristotle and Peripatetic tradition), his studies are accepted to be central as it includes re-definition of a cluster of problems and doctrines that are part of the ancient and late ancient logic. Avicenna differs as he introduces new distinctions. Among others, he added new concepts and distinctions that are not found in the writings of the ancient logicians. He improved Aristotelian categorical and modal syllogistics. As such, Avicenna’s logic is still one of the most fruitful and important destinations for studies conducted in the field of logic both in Eastern and Western worlds. In this context, Nicholas Rescher takes an important place as he is one of the most important philosophers introducing and explaining the Arabic logic into the West. For instance, among others, Rescher takes into consideration Avicenna’s contradiction and conversion, hypothetical propositions, contrariety, subcontrariety and subalternation (Karimullah, 2014, 24). Rescher has also more general claims about the origins and development of the Arabic logic. For instance, analyzing Avicenna and Arabic logic, he claims that Arabic logic “ … developed wholly in the wake of the classical Greek tradition as preserved in, and transmitted through Hellenistic Aristotelianism” ( 1963, 13). Accordingly, in this presentation I will examine Rescher’s treatment of Avicenna’s logic. Using Rescher’s studies on Arabic logic in general and Avicenna’s logic in particular, my main aim is to draw a frame concerning the virtues and criticisms about Rescher’s interpretation of the Avicenna’s logic. This will provide a frame as to how Avicenna’s logic is conceived in Western World. In addition, at the end of my analysis I hope to shed a light into the place Avicenna takes in the history of logic in general and Arabic logic in particular.
Oriens, 2015
Avicenna's (d. 1037) theory of demonstration is largely inspired by Aristotle's Posterior Analytics but also, at the same time, characterized by significant flashes of originality. One of the areas where Avicenna's innovative contribution is most evident is his interpretation of the notion of necessity in the context of demonstrative arguments. The paper investigates two issues. First, the relationship between the notion of substantial necessity and that of descriptional necessity and their relevance for Avicenna's theory of scientific discourse. Second, the question whether Barbara lxl qualifies as a genuine demonstrative argument, i.e., whether its combination of modalized premises provides sufficiently strong epistemic grounds for certitude to come about in the conclusion of a syllogism.
2019
In the present research, the aim was to examine some of the metaphysical foundations of knowledge from the view point of Avicenna whose theories of knowledge were influentially echoed in the epistemic theories in the Islamic world and the next schools of thought. The main problem with the statement of current research is a critical question of whether Avicenna’s metaphysical foundations are capable of forming a representative operation for our knowledge that is accurately representing the external world. If his metaphysical foundations fail to justify the fact that our knowledge represents the real world as it is, the metaphysical foundations of his epistemology, in spite of his realism, would inevitably slip into a fundamental gap between the known-object and the knower-subject. Such research on the principles of epistemology of Avicenna who is one of the pioneers of major thought stream in Islamic philosophy i.e. Peripatetic philosophy, can open up new perspectives for further sys...
This paper argues that, in spite of interpretations to the contrary, Avicenna and Aquinas are fundamentally agreed as to subject and principles of metaphysics. The first part shows the philosophers' common metaphysical starting points in the realm of assent and the realm of conceptualization as well as their common use of the distinction between principles common by causality and common by predication to provide the overall structure for their metaphysics (Avicenna, Physics of the Shifa' 1.2.8–10; Aquinas, De Trin. V.4). The second part argues that both philosophers have similar descriptions of God and common being and thus similar views on the relation between God and the subject of metaphysics; and the third part, by surveying some remarks by Avicenna on Sufism and the use of the Qur'ān's description of God's attributes, argues that Avicenna is not forced by his naturalistic theory of prophecy to include God under the subject of metaphysics.
The paper offers some observations with a view to correcting ostensible misunderstandings of the so-called New Natural Law ("NNL") theory, concluding that the NNL theory is unworkable and unsustainable, even on its own terms. It is argued that the NNL theory is based on fundamental misunderstandings of the nature of necessity in Aquinas; the nature of propositions which are "known in themselves" (per se nota); and the nature of fundamental practical reasoning.
2016
ion 39; Abraham D. Stone: Simplicius and Avicenna on the essential corporeity of material substance 73; David C. Reisman: Avicenna at the ARCE 131-182. ———. 2003. Avicenna's Metaphysics in Context. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. 75. ———. 2003. "Towards a history of Avicenna's distinction between immanent and transcendent causes." In Before and After Avicenna. Proceedings of the First Conference of the Avicenna Study Group, edited by Reisman, David C. and Al-Rahim, Ahmed H., 49-68. Leiden: Brill. 76. ———. 2005. "Avicenna and the Avicennian Tradition." In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, edited by Adamson, Peter and Taylor, Richard, 92-136. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. "My aim in this book is to present a history of the metaphysics of Abú `Ali al-Husayn ibn `Abdallah ibn Sinâ, known in the West by his Latinized name Avicenna. Since 1937, when Amélie-Marie Goichon published La distinction de l'essence et de l'existence ...
The philosophical masterpiece of Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā, d. 1037), the Kitāb al-Šifāʾ (Book of the Cure), is an extensive summa with four main parts (logic, natural philosophy, mathematics, and metaphysics). The three first parts are further divided into distinct sections (nine sections of logic, eight of natural philosophy, and four of mathematics). The metaphysical part, despite consisting of a single section, includes at the end a succinct treatment of practical philosophy. One remarkable aspect of this massive work is the connection between the parts dealing with logic and natural philosophy, on the one hand, and the part devoted to metaphysics, on the other. Thus, some metaphysical doctrines are announced either in logic or in natural philosophy: Avicenna informs the reader that further developments of certain logical or physical issues will be found in metaphysics, since the scientific scope of logic and physics is limited. Conversely, many logical or physical doctrines are quoted in metaphysics: Avicenna summarizes these doctrines in order to use them in metaphysics, taking them as already sufficiently clarified in logic and physics. 1 A more peculiar -and, in my opinion, more interesting -type of 'interface' between logic and physics, on the one side, and metaphysics, on the other, is the case of logical or physical doctrines repeated in metaphysics: there are certain doctrines already developed in logic and physics which Avicenna expounds extensively in metaphysics for a second time. This third case
The Metaphysics Within Physics, 2007
Philosophical analyses may be pursued via a myriad of methods in service of as great a multitude of goals. Frequently the data upon which an analysis rests, and from which it receives its original inspiration, recount systematic connections between diverse realms of discourse or diverse sets of facts, events, actions, or objects. The aim of the project is elucidating the underlying logical, conceptual, or ontological structure that accounts for these connections. As an obvious example, John's beliefs about what Sarah knows covary systematically with his beliefs about what Sarah believes, about what Sarah has good evidence for, and about what is actually the case. We may explain these covariations by postulating that John at least tacitly adheres to the theory that knowledge is some species of justified true belief. The results of such a preliminary investigation of correlations among beliefs may be put to various uses. If we choose to endorse John's theory we will simply assert that what Sarah believes, what Sarah has good evidence for, and what is true determine what she knows. We may endorse John's theory, as revealed by his inferences, but criticize his particular judgements. For example, John's inferences may imply that he takes knowledge to require infallible evidence and so, by his own lights, he should not ascribe knowledge to Sarah since her evidence is not conclusive. Or we may instead endorse John's judgements and recommend that he amend his inferences accordingly. And, of course, the inferences, particular judgements, and intuitions at issue may be our own. This essay was written in 1989, but being too long for a journal and too short for a book only circulated informally. There are evident similarities to John Carroll's approach in his Laws of Nature (1994), and we have both been identified as primitivists about laws. I have not attempted a direct comparison between our views as it would not fit into the structure of the paper as originally conceived.
Academia.edu, 2013
The famous argument for the existence of God is analyzed with a survey of the Greek and Arabic influences of Avicenna's system. Turning to the text, The Salvation, ‘’Metaphysics,’’ II. 12, it is stated that ‘’at any one and the same time there cannot be for anything that is possible in itself a cause that is possible ad infinitum’’ (II.12.2). Here he’s saying that a possible being cannot have an infinite amount of causes at the same time. Because if that infinite totality of causes would itself have either an internal cause or an external necessary cause. It can’t be internal, because it would either be (a) necessary, which is not an option because everything internal to that totality is possible; then (b) an internal possible cause – which is not an option because that would make it a part of the totality and a part can’t be a cause of the whole. So if that cause is not internal, then it has to be external. It can’t be possible, because all of the possible causes have been established in that inner totality. Therefore it has to be necessary. He concludes the argument by stating that: Thus, things existing possibly terminate in a cause existing necessarily, in which case not every effect that exists as something possible will have simultaneously with it a cause that exists as something possible, and so an infinite number of causes existing at a single time is impossible. (II.12.2) This argument can be considered as a subsidiary conclusion to Avicenna’s main argument for the proof of God’s existence (McGinnis 166-67). There are considered to be four main categories of arguments: (1) the metaphysical proof from necessity; (2) the proof from movement; (3) the proof from causality; (4) the proof from ontology (Netton 172-73). The themes are similar to the discussions on the problem of infinite causal regress as discussed for example in book two of Alexander of Aphrodisias’ On Aristotle’s Metaphysics. I think that he is essentially concerned with establishing a logical argument that integrates a hierarchy of ontological causality rather than simply natural causality. In that sense, it could be considered similar to the ‘’a posteriori cosmological arguments’’ of the quinque via of ThomasAquinas (Netton 173).
1. The problem of identii cation and the problem of inference A main issue in the literature on laws is to dee ne criteria which would permit to distinguish genuine lawlike propositions from universally true propositions which describe merely accidental or fortuitous regularities in the world, such as all gold objects have a mass inferior to fty tons, to reformulate a well-known example due to Hans Reichenbach. This is the epistemological problem of identii cation. The challenge here is to formulate criteria, in the sense of suff cient conditions at least, which would justify attributing the title of law to a universally true proposition. If those criteria are satiss ed by the proposition, then we know that it is a law and that it does not just happen to be accidentally true. This is the task that Humean regularists set to themselves. Since, for them, lawlike propositions describe worldly regularities, their aim is to nd criteria which are consistent with their empiricist position and to refrain from introducing ingredients which would go beyond the realm of what is empirically accessible. In other words, serious empiricists are required to shun any kind of metaphysics. As we will see such endeavor is fraught with all sorts of diff culties. On this I agree with van Fraassen who is, in his own words, a " immoderate empiricist " (2000, 1660) and consistently sustains that there are no laws, in the sense that the search for empirically satisfactory criteria which would divide regularities into two distinct classes, lawful and unlawful, is bound to fail. Simply because there is no empirical fact, that is, some empirically detectable special kind of regularities, which would legitimate endowing the propositions which describe them with the title of law. Surely, some regularities are more general than others, but they all are regularities in the rst place and no empirical feature is available which would permit to single out some regularities and endow them with some privileged status. This is why the empiricists who would like to retain the distinction between laws and non-laws, just as scientists do, attempted to devise criteria which are internal to
Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale, 2010
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.