
Guido Melchior
Supervisors: Keith Lehrer and Reinhard Kamitz
less
Related Authors
Georgi Gardiner
University of Oxford
Michael Blome-Tillmann
McGill University
Giada Fratantonio
University of Edinburgh
Lewis Ross
London School of Economics and Political Science
David Enoch
The Hebrew University of Jerusalem
Clayton Littlejohn
King's College London
Christian Dahlman
Lund University
Renee Jorgensen
The University Of Michigan
TALIA FISHER
Tel Aviv University
Uploads
Papers by Guido Melchior
court, whose values exceed the value of knowledge in certain contexts. Moreover, the values of these other epistemic standings do not always rely on the value of knowledge. In terms of value, knowledge is not an outstanding epistemic concept. Hence, in terms of value we cannot find support for the privileged position that knowledge enjoys in epistemology.
Kelly Becker, Marian David, Nenad Miščević, Wes Siscoe, and Danilo Šuster on my
Knowing and Checking: An Epistemological Investigation (Routledge 2019), hereinafter abbreviated as KC. These papers resulted from a workshop organized by the
department of philosophy of the University of Maribor. I am very thankful to the
organizers of the workshop and to the authors for their comments.
of bootstrapping. On the one hand, bootstrapping is
not a persuasive method of settling questions about the
reliability of a source. On the other hand, our beliefs that
our sense apparatus is reliable is based on other empirically
formed beliefs, that is, they are acquired via a presumably
complex bootstrapping process. I will argue that when we
doubt the reliability of a source, bootstrapping is not a persuasive
method for coming to believe that the source is reliable.
However, when being initially unaware of a source and
its reliability, as in the case of forming beliefs about our sense
apparatus, bootstrapping can be eventually persuasive.
court, whose values exceed the value of knowledge in certain contexts. Moreover, the values of these other epistemic standings do not always rely on the value of knowledge. In terms of value, knowledge is not an outstanding epistemic concept. Hence, in terms of value we cannot find support for the privileged position that knowledge enjoys in epistemology.
Kelly Becker, Marian David, Nenad Miščević, Wes Siscoe, and Danilo Šuster on my
Knowing and Checking: An Epistemological Investigation (Routledge 2019), hereinafter abbreviated as KC. These papers resulted from a workshop organized by the
department of philosophy of the University of Maribor. I am very thankful to the
organizers of the workshop and to the authors for their comments.
of bootstrapping. On the one hand, bootstrapping is
not a persuasive method of settling questions about the
reliability of a source. On the other hand, our beliefs that
our sense apparatus is reliable is based on other empirically
formed beliefs, that is, they are acquired via a presumably
complex bootstrapping process. I will argue that when we
doubt the reliability of a source, bootstrapping is not a persuasive
method for coming to believe that the source is reliable.
However, when being initially unaware of a source and
its reliability, as in the case of forming beliefs about our sense
apparatus, bootstrapping can be eventually persuasive.
(1) It breaks new ground by developing the first thorough epistemic theory of checking.
(2) It provides a novel explanation of enduring epistemological problems, such as the skeptical problem, via a theory of checking instead of, as is the usual strategy, by a theory of knowledge.
(3) It settles a lively debate in epistemology by arguing that sensitivity is necessary for checking but not for knowing, thereby finding a new home for the much discussed modal sensitivity principle.