
Michel Ghins
Related Authors
Mauricio Suárez
Universidad Complutense de Madrid
Martin Kusch
University of Vienna
Marc Champagne
Kwantlen Polytechnic University
David Seamon
Kansas State University
Armando Marques-Guedes
UNL - New University of Lisbon
Fausto Fraisopi
Aix-Marseille University
Eros Carvalho
Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul
Didier COSTE
Université Bordeaux-Montaigne
Marcin Miłkowski
Polish Academy of Sciences
Prof. Dr. Raffaele Pisano, MSc, HDR (Habil.)
Université des Sciences et Technologies de Lille (Lille-1)
InterestsView All (10)
Uploads
Papers by Michel Ghins
Making sense of quantum dynamics
I propose four stringent requirements for rationally believing that an unobserved object posited by a theory possesses a specific property. Firstly, this property must be an OP property. Secondly, it must be measurable. Thirdly, it must play a causal role in producing the observed data. Fourthly, distinct independent methods for measuring this property must deliver concordant results. I then show that the generality and acceptability of these four criteria is grounded on a parallelism with the reasons we adduce for (rightly) believing in the existence of ordinary observable things which we don’t immediately perceive such as mice, in some circumstances. However, an agnostic attitude is to be recommended with respect to the possession of PT properties by an object posited by an - even successful - scientific theory.
The book begins with an analysis of the origin of what the author calls “dualism” – both in its ontological and epistemological versions (29) – in which he correctly locates the source of contemporary relativist and antirealist views on science. Ontological dualism goes back to the ancient Greeks and divides the world into “surface appearances” and “deep authentic realities”. In its epistemological version, dualism appears with the birth of modern science in the 17th century. Epistemological dualism postulates a dichotomy between our ideas or mental representations, which are supposedly immediately known to us, and reality itself. Such division raises the question of the faithfulness of our representations to the realities which they are meant to represent (245). But this problem has no satisfactory solution. Once a wedge is driven between ideas and things, we are inevitably drawn to a sceptical attitude with respect to science’s capacity to reach knowledge of reality.
By embracing a realist position, Agazzi stands against dualism: science aims at knowing what is real, including some unobservable entities, and manages to do so, albeit only partially.
Descartes en effet, tous les changements dans la nature résultent en définitive
de collisions, et de collisions seulement. Mais si la loi des chocs - et les
sept règles qui la suivent dans les Principes de la philosophie2 - sont claires
en elles-mêmes, l’argumentation développée par Descartes en leur faveur continue
de susciter la perplexité des commentateurs. Je tenterai, en m’inspirant
principalement des travaux de Gabbey (1980) et Garber (1999), de dégager les
principes sur lesquels reposent les sept règles déterministes des chocs. Je
montrerai que ces sept règles peuvent être déduites de trois conditions.
J’examinerai ensuite les fondements dynamiques de ces trois conditions et de la
théorie cartésienne des chocs pour en relever les difficultés.
Making sense of quantum dynamics
I propose four stringent requirements for rationally believing that an unobserved object posited by a theory possesses a specific property. Firstly, this property must be an OP property. Secondly, it must be measurable. Thirdly, it must play a causal role in producing the observed data. Fourthly, distinct independent methods for measuring this property must deliver concordant results. I then show that the generality and acceptability of these four criteria is grounded on a parallelism with the reasons we adduce for (rightly) believing in the existence of ordinary observable things which we don’t immediately perceive such as mice, in some circumstances. However, an agnostic attitude is to be recommended with respect to the possession of PT properties by an object posited by an - even successful - scientific theory.
The book begins with an analysis of the origin of what the author calls “dualism” – both in its ontological and epistemological versions (29) – in which he correctly locates the source of contemporary relativist and antirealist views on science. Ontological dualism goes back to the ancient Greeks and divides the world into “surface appearances” and “deep authentic realities”. In its epistemological version, dualism appears with the birth of modern science in the 17th century. Epistemological dualism postulates a dichotomy between our ideas or mental representations, which are supposedly immediately known to us, and reality itself. Such division raises the question of the faithfulness of our representations to the realities which they are meant to represent (245). But this problem has no satisfactory solution. Once a wedge is driven between ideas and things, we are inevitably drawn to a sceptical attitude with respect to science’s capacity to reach knowledge of reality.
By embracing a realist position, Agazzi stands against dualism: science aims at knowing what is real, including some unobservable entities, and manages to do so, albeit only partially.
Descartes en effet, tous les changements dans la nature résultent en définitive
de collisions, et de collisions seulement. Mais si la loi des chocs - et les
sept règles qui la suivent dans les Principes de la philosophie2 - sont claires
en elles-mêmes, l’argumentation développée par Descartes en leur faveur continue
de susciter la perplexité des commentateurs. Je tenterai, en m’inspirant
principalement des travaux de Gabbey (1980) et Garber (1999), de dégager les
principes sur lesquels reposent les sept règles déterministes des chocs. Je
montrerai que ces sept règles peuvent être déduites de trois conditions.
J’examinerai ensuite les fondements dynamiques de ces trois conditions et de la
théorie cartésienne des chocs pour en relever les difficultés.
ser considerada verdadeira? Vários debates atuais da filosofia
da ciência convergem para essa questão. Trata-se, primeiramente,
de uma questão epistemológica, pois diz respeito ao
alcance e aos limites do conhecimento científico. Todavia, é
também uma questão metafísica, visto que nos impõe uma
interrogação sobre a natureza das entidades postuladas pelas
teorias científicas. No presente livro, o leitor terá oportunidade
de se informar e refletir sobre uma concepção realista
acerca das teorias científicas. Ser realista, aqui, significa
acreditar que as leis científicas são – ao menos parcial e
aproximativamente – verdadeiras e que os modelos teóricos
também representam estruturas inacessíveis à percepção
sensível imediata. No âmbito dessa perspectiva realista, o
autor discute e critica as concepções das leis científicas
propostas pelos neorregularistas inspirados em Hume, de um
lado, e pelos chamados necessitaristas categorialistas, tais
como Armstrong, Dretske e Tooley, de outro lado. Em contrapartida
a esses modos de pensar, o autor oferece uma concepção
baseada numa metafísica neoaristotélica da
natureza. Buscar as razões para aceitar a existência
de poderes causais ou disposições aos quais se
possa atribuir os fundamentos metafísicos das
regularidades encontradas na natureza e, ao
mesmo tempo, da verdade de proposições
contrafactuais – eis o desafio a que se propôs o
autor e que lhe serve como inspiração e ocasião
para apresentar a seu leitor as questões centrais
da filosofia da ciência neste início do séc. XXI.