
Kym Maclaren
Phone: 416.979.5000 ext. 2700
Address: Ryerson University
Toronto, ON
Address: Ryerson University
Toronto, ON
less
Related Authors
Noel B. Salazar
KU Leuven
Galen Strawson
The University of Texas at Austin
Matthew Broome
University of Oxford
Laura Caulfield
University of Wolverhampton
Cirus Rinaldi
Università degli Studi di Palermo
Ruben López-Cano
Escola Superior de Música de Catalunya
Liam J . Leonard
University Of Winchester
Babette Babich
Fordham University
Shaun Gallagher
University of Memphis
Cor Baerveldt
University of Alberta
InterestsView All (18)
Uploads
Papers by Kym Maclaren
Citation: “Singularity as Becoming Oneself through Others: Lessons from Merleau-Ponty, Laing, and Anorexia” eds. Stefan Kristensen and Till Grohman., special issue on Self and Singularity, Metodo: International Studies in Phenomenology and Philosophy 7 (2019): 37-73.
The chapter draws upon the notion of dialectic suggested by Plato’s Socrates, the idea of seriality developed by Sartre, and the insights of students of Walls to Bridges classes.
Citation: “From Walls to Bridges: Education as Dialectic and the Educator as Curator of the Affective Conditions of Dialogue” in _Teaching in Unequal Societies_, edited by John Russon, Siby K George and Pravesh Jung. New Delhi: Bloomsbury, (2020): 122-149.
In this essay, I propose that human development is the emergence of something significantly new out of a past situation that does not hold that novel achievement as a determinate potential except retrospectively. Development, in other words, might best be understood as a “realization” in the sense of a making-real of some new form of being that had no prior place in reality, that was not programmed in advance, but that once realized can have its roots traced back to determinate conditions and potentials in its own past. This amounts to a rethinking of the nature of developmental potential as retrospectively determined. But it also involves a reconception of the locus of such potential: I argue that developmental potential must be understood as located in the human-organism-in-its-situation, rather than simply in the human organism. I take my bearings from phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and I make my case by elucidating three different forms of human development described by Merleau-Ponty: intellectual realizations of insight; the realization of a new perceptual-motor skill; and a child’s realization of a new lived way of making sense of the interpersonal world.
My aim in this essay is, drawing upon Merleau-Ponty’s mid-career writings, including the lectures on institution, to bring out the full force of this claim. My focus is on the more personal side of institutions—that is to say, transformational moments within our personal and intersubjective lives where a new configuration of meaning and a new form of agency is inaugurated—and on what Merleau-Ponty calls the “subterranean logic” of this development. The development involved is “subterranean,” as we will see, insofar as these transformational moments come in some sense from beyond the subject and are not simply the result of the subject’s own constitutive powers. The notion of institution is thus yet another way in which Merleau-Ponty seeks to criticize and offer an alternative to intellectualism, with its idea of a constituting subject.
For the sake of introducing this Special Issue, this introduction outlines the special contribution that phenomenology and its notion of embodiment can make to understanding intimacy; it lays out some of the key resources on which phenomenological accounts draw in order to understand intimacy; and it proposes that intimacy must be understood as conditioned by our embodiment and as a process of significant others becoming a part of our embodiment by virtue of informing the very way the world reveals itself and the meaning we find therein. The introduction ends with a summary of the contributions to this issue, noting that their diverse elucidations of intimacies through the notion of embodiment lead as a whole to a revelation of the central place of intimacy in self-transformation and our becoming individuals.
Table of Contents can be found here: http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/17554586/13/supp/C
If you'd like a copy, please email me: [email protected]
conceptions of embodiment and passivity. Through a critical assessment of
cognitive theories of emotion, and in particular Solomon's theory, it argues (1) that
there is a sense in which emotions may be judgments, so long as we understand such judgments as bodily enactments of meaning, but (2) that even understood in this way, the notion of judgment (or construal) can only account for a subset of emotions which I call "emotional clichés," and not for authentic passions. In contrast with Solomon's account which conceives the subject as constituting, this account of
emotion requires us to understand subjectivity as moved by meanings in the world,
and as sometimes, in an authentic passion, dispossessed by those meanings.
This essay offers a criticism of this moralistic conception of agency and selfhood, and it does so through a consideration of emotion and the emotional metamorphoses that we can undergo—either towards increasingly compulsive, “mad” ways of being, or towards new epiphanies and a new sense of oneself and one’s place in the world. Relying upon an existential understanding of the “subject as agent” as an achievement, or what one becomes, rather than as a pre-given, always present entity, I argue that emotion is not opposed to reason, but is rather an essential element of our rational development towards autonomous ways of being. The moralistic conception of the subject, on this account, is wrong to think that a person’s emotional behaviour is simply her own fault, as if she had allowed herself to fall away from a rationality to which she has access; it mistakenly presupposes a fully developed rational self, and simultaneously fails to recognize the essential role that others play in a person’s emotional metamorphoses. As a result, the moralistic conception of the subject can, I suggest, be oppressive and destructive, actually helping to bring about “mad” and compulsive behaviour, instead of inspiring a greater rationality, as it hopes to do.
To make these claims, I draw on the phenomenological tradition of philosophy, and especially on the work of Martin Heidegger and Maurice Merleau-Ponty.
Books by Kym Maclaren
“The rich and impressive essays in Time, Memory, Institution make a new and significant contribution to the field, dealing with works of Merleau-Ponty’s that have only recently become available in English.” Jack Reynolds, author of Merleau-Ponty and Derrida: Intertwining Embodiment and Alterity
This collection is the first extended investigation of the relation between time and memory in Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s thought as a whole as well as the first to explore in depth the significance of his concept of institution. It brings the French phenomenologist’s views on the self and ontology into contemporary focus. Time, Memory, Institution argues that the self is not a self-contained or self-determining identity, as such, but is gathered out of a radical openness to what is not self, and that it gathers itself in a time that is not merely a given dimension, but folds back upon, gathers, and institutes itself.
Access to previously unavailable texts, in particular Merleau-Ponty’s lectures on institution and expression, has presented scholars with new resources for thinking about time, memory, and history. These essays represent the best of this new direction in scholarship; they deepen our understanding of self and world in relation to time and memory; and they give occasion to reexamine Merleau-Ponty’s contribution and relevance to contemporary Continental philosophy.
This volume is essential reading for scholars of phenomenology and French philosophy, as well as for the many readers across the arts, humanities, and social sciences who continue to draw insight and inspiration from Merleau-Ponty.
Contributors: Elizabeth Behnke, Edward Casey, Véronique Fóti, Donald Landes, Kirsten Jacobson, Galen Johnson, Michael Kelly, Scott Marratto, Glen Mazis, Caterina Rea, John Russon, Robert Vallier, and Bernhard Waldenfels
Citation: “Singularity as Becoming Oneself through Others: Lessons from Merleau-Ponty, Laing, and Anorexia” eds. Stefan Kristensen and Till Grohman., special issue on Self and Singularity, Metodo: International Studies in Phenomenology and Philosophy 7 (2019): 37-73.
The chapter draws upon the notion of dialectic suggested by Plato’s Socrates, the idea of seriality developed by Sartre, and the insights of students of Walls to Bridges classes.
Citation: “From Walls to Bridges: Education as Dialectic and the Educator as Curator of the Affective Conditions of Dialogue” in _Teaching in Unequal Societies_, edited by John Russon, Siby K George and Pravesh Jung. New Delhi: Bloomsbury, (2020): 122-149.
In this essay, I propose that human development is the emergence of something significantly new out of a past situation that does not hold that novel achievement as a determinate potential except retrospectively. Development, in other words, might best be understood as a “realization” in the sense of a making-real of some new form of being that had no prior place in reality, that was not programmed in advance, but that once realized can have its roots traced back to determinate conditions and potentials in its own past. This amounts to a rethinking of the nature of developmental potential as retrospectively determined. But it also involves a reconception of the locus of such potential: I argue that developmental potential must be understood as located in the human-organism-in-its-situation, rather than simply in the human organism. I take my bearings from phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and I make my case by elucidating three different forms of human development described by Merleau-Ponty: intellectual realizations of insight; the realization of a new perceptual-motor skill; and a child’s realization of a new lived way of making sense of the interpersonal world.
My aim in this essay is, drawing upon Merleau-Ponty’s mid-career writings, including the lectures on institution, to bring out the full force of this claim. My focus is on the more personal side of institutions—that is to say, transformational moments within our personal and intersubjective lives where a new configuration of meaning and a new form of agency is inaugurated—and on what Merleau-Ponty calls the “subterranean logic” of this development. The development involved is “subterranean,” as we will see, insofar as these transformational moments come in some sense from beyond the subject and are not simply the result of the subject’s own constitutive powers. The notion of institution is thus yet another way in which Merleau-Ponty seeks to criticize and offer an alternative to intellectualism, with its idea of a constituting subject.
For the sake of introducing this Special Issue, this introduction outlines the special contribution that phenomenology and its notion of embodiment can make to understanding intimacy; it lays out some of the key resources on which phenomenological accounts draw in order to understand intimacy; and it proposes that intimacy must be understood as conditioned by our embodiment and as a process of significant others becoming a part of our embodiment by virtue of informing the very way the world reveals itself and the meaning we find therein. The introduction ends with a summary of the contributions to this issue, noting that their diverse elucidations of intimacies through the notion of embodiment lead as a whole to a revelation of the central place of intimacy in self-transformation and our becoming individuals.
Table of Contents can be found here: http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/17554586/13/supp/C
If you'd like a copy, please email me: [email protected]
conceptions of embodiment and passivity. Through a critical assessment of
cognitive theories of emotion, and in particular Solomon's theory, it argues (1) that
there is a sense in which emotions may be judgments, so long as we understand such judgments as bodily enactments of meaning, but (2) that even understood in this way, the notion of judgment (or construal) can only account for a subset of emotions which I call "emotional clichés," and not for authentic passions. In contrast with Solomon's account which conceives the subject as constituting, this account of
emotion requires us to understand subjectivity as moved by meanings in the world,
and as sometimes, in an authentic passion, dispossessed by those meanings.
This essay offers a criticism of this moralistic conception of agency and selfhood, and it does so through a consideration of emotion and the emotional metamorphoses that we can undergo—either towards increasingly compulsive, “mad” ways of being, or towards new epiphanies and a new sense of oneself and one’s place in the world. Relying upon an existential understanding of the “subject as agent” as an achievement, or what one becomes, rather than as a pre-given, always present entity, I argue that emotion is not opposed to reason, but is rather an essential element of our rational development towards autonomous ways of being. The moralistic conception of the subject, on this account, is wrong to think that a person’s emotional behaviour is simply her own fault, as if she had allowed herself to fall away from a rationality to which she has access; it mistakenly presupposes a fully developed rational self, and simultaneously fails to recognize the essential role that others play in a person’s emotional metamorphoses. As a result, the moralistic conception of the subject can, I suggest, be oppressive and destructive, actually helping to bring about “mad” and compulsive behaviour, instead of inspiring a greater rationality, as it hopes to do.
To make these claims, I draw on the phenomenological tradition of philosophy, and especially on the work of Martin Heidegger and Maurice Merleau-Ponty.
“The rich and impressive essays in Time, Memory, Institution make a new and significant contribution to the field, dealing with works of Merleau-Ponty’s that have only recently become available in English.” Jack Reynolds, author of Merleau-Ponty and Derrida: Intertwining Embodiment and Alterity
This collection is the first extended investigation of the relation between time and memory in Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s thought as a whole as well as the first to explore in depth the significance of his concept of institution. It brings the French phenomenologist’s views on the self and ontology into contemporary focus. Time, Memory, Institution argues that the self is not a self-contained or self-determining identity, as such, but is gathered out of a radical openness to what is not self, and that it gathers itself in a time that is not merely a given dimension, but folds back upon, gathers, and institutes itself.
Access to previously unavailable texts, in particular Merleau-Ponty’s lectures on institution and expression, has presented scholars with new resources for thinking about time, memory, and history. These essays represent the best of this new direction in scholarship; they deepen our understanding of self and world in relation to time and memory; and they give occasion to reexamine Merleau-Ponty’s contribution and relevance to contemporary Continental philosophy.
This volume is essential reading for scholars of phenomenology and French philosophy, as well as for the many readers across the arts, humanities, and social sciences who continue to draw insight and inspiration from Merleau-Ponty.
Contributors: Elizabeth Behnke, Edward Casey, Véronique Fóti, Donald Landes, Kirsten Jacobson, Galen Johnson, Michael Kelly, Scott Marratto, Glen Mazis, Caterina Rea, John Russon, Robert Vallier, and Bernhard Waldenfels