
Ariel Zemach
J.S.D. (Columbia University School of Law).
Senior Lecturer, Ono Academic College, Faculty of Law.
Senior Lecturer, Ono Academic College, Faculty of Law.
less
Related Authors
Kastle Lund-Turner
University of the Pacific
Nicolas Cornell
University of Michigan Law School
Uploads
Papers by Ariel Zemach
This article argues that the purposes of the norm against unjust enrichment – promoting individual justice between parties and removing incentives for wrongful conduct – require its application in international law to the indirect enrichment of a state as a result of internationally harmful conduct by its taxpayers. Such application of the international norm against unjust enrichment is particularly important because of (a) evidentiary difficulties in the international arena, which significantly erode the efficacy of the remedial regime that is based on the rules concerning the responsibility of states for internationally wrongful conduct; (b) the unavailability in international law of a cause of action against private actors engaging in internationally harmful conduct; and (c) the limited capacity of a state harmed by the conduct to recover from such actors under its domestic legal system. The article suggests that the purview of the international norm against unjust enrichment extends to situations of an indirect link between the loss of the claimant state and the gain of the enriched state, provided that such link is sufficiently close.
The West Bank is a territory under Israeli occupation, and annexation by an occupier of any part of the occupied territory violates international law. The Article argues, however, that the illegal annexation by Israel of an occupied territory would make that territory a part of Israel for the limited purpose of the right to citizenship, as an exception to the principle that illegal annexation is null and void. Hence, the existing and emerging IHRL obligations of Israel to grant citizenship to residents of territory acquired by Israel extend to Palestinians residing in areas of the West Bank illegally annexed by Israel.
The Article argues further that, for the purpose of applying the norms of IHRL that concern the right to citizenship, the definition of annexation extends beyond formal annexation and encompasses de facto annexation as well. Annexation of occupied territory results from the occupier’s display of sovereignty in that territory, among other things, by settling its own population in the occupied territory. In view of the current spread of Israeli settlements across the West Bank, unless Israel removes, within a reasonable time period, many of these settlements, the entire territory of the West Bank may be considered to have been annexed, and the entire Palestinian population of the West Bank would have a strong claim to Israeli citizenship under an emerging norm of international law.
The article also examines the role of international recognition of title to territory in the resolution of the territorial dispute between Israel and the Palestinians. To what extent does international law empower the international community to resolve a territorial dispute over the objection of an affected party, by pronouncing a collective position that reflects near-consensus? The article concludes that a collective recognition by the international community of Palestinian title to territories currently occupied by Israel would have neither a probative value nor a constitutive effect under international law, unless such international position takes the form of U.N. Security Council action in the exercise of its binding powers under Chapter VII of the U.N. Charter.
The article further demonstrates that international law does not support an Israeli claim to sovereignty over the occupied West Bank. This inquiry focuses on a critical examination of a theory recently advanced in legal literature, which predicates such a claim on the doctrine of uti possidetis juris. Finally, the article considers the consequences of the absence of a norm of international law governing the demarcation of the border between Israel and the Palestinians.
The advisory regime would represent a bargain between the Security Council and operating states, which would grant protection for states against the costs that typically attach to non-compliance with the law of war, to the extent that the state followed the legal guidance provided by the international advisors. This article demonstrates that the powers of the Security Council under the U.N. Charter accommodate such a bargain.
The desirability of the proposed advisory regime from a humanitarian perspective, and its appeal for states, depend on the interpretive approach to the law of war that would guide the international advisors. This article identifies an interpretive approach to the law of war that would make the proposed advisory regime the best bargain from a humanitarian perspective that is politically feasible. Such an interpretive approach marks the farthest a state would be willing to stray from the most permissive interpretive approach to the law of war made possible by the indeterminacy of the law to secure the benefits that the advisory regime offers. Use of such an interpretive approach would be secured through the selection of international advisors, tailored to ensure that they are inclined to embrace the desired interpretive approach.
1. When is the threat sufficiently proximate to justify the use of lethal force against the suspected terrorist?
2. Can a state engage in counter-terrorism operations that are likely to result in the unintentional killing of innocent persons?
Far from limiting the reach of universal jurisdiction, the proposed reform would enhance the fight against impunity by diffusing current objections to the exercise of universal jurisdiction in absentia, thereby facilitating the assertion of such jurisdiction by states.
The author argues that international human rights law does not prohibit the repatriation of Israeli settlers. No provision of an international human rights treaty brings the non-repatriation plea of Israeli settlers within the realm of a protected human right. Even if it were possible to point to such a provision, the repatriation of Israeli settlers would probably be permitted under the balancing of interest regime that generally prevails in international human rights law.
The article proceeds to examine the protection granted to illegally implanted settlers under the rules of customary international law that determine the legal consequences of state conduct that violates international law ("State Responsibility Rules"). State Responsibility Rules generally require a state that violated international law to eliminate the consequences of such violation, but the Rules may exempt the violating state from this obligation in view of the interests of individuals. The article shows that examining whether international human rights law prohibits the repatriation of illegally implanted settlers is fundamentally different from examining whether State Responsibility Rules exempt the occupant from carrying out repatriation. The interests of individual settlers may attain sufficient legal significance to support an exemption for an occupant from its duty under State Responsibility Rules to eliminate the consequences of its illegal settlement activity (i.e., the duty to repatriate the settlers) even in the absence of a human rights law prohibition against repatriation. Such an exemption does not depend on a robust balancing-of-interests analysis of the type that prevails in international human rights law. Rather, State Responsibility Rules seem to exempt an occupant from the obligation to repatriate illegally implanted settlers whenever the imposition of such obligation would result in the forcible eviction of a large number of individuals. The author argues that a case for such an exemption has emerged with regard to the settlers implanted by Israel in the occupied Palestinian territories. The article maintains further that the absence of a duty to repatriate the settlers allows for a strong argument in favor of including the interest in non-repatriation within the sphere of interests that Israel may legitimately promote in negotiating the end of occupation.
This article argues that the purposes of the norm against unjust enrichment – promoting individual justice between parties and removing incentives for wrongful conduct – require its application in international law to the indirect enrichment of a state as a result of internationally harmful conduct by its taxpayers. Such application of the international norm against unjust enrichment is particularly important because of (a) evidentiary difficulties in the international arena, which significantly erode the efficacy of the remedial regime that is based on the rules concerning the responsibility of states for internationally wrongful conduct; (b) the unavailability in international law of a cause of action against private actors engaging in internationally harmful conduct; and (c) the limited capacity of a state harmed by the conduct to recover from such actors under its domestic legal system. The article suggests that the purview of the international norm against unjust enrichment extends to situations of an indirect link between the loss of the claimant state and the gain of the enriched state, provided that such link is sufficiently close.
The West Bank is a territory under Israeli occupation, and annexation by an occupier of any part of the occupied territory violates international law. The Article argues, however, that the illegal annexation by Israel of an occupied territory would make that territory a part of Israel for the limited purpose of the right to citizenship, as an exception to the principle that illegal annexation is null and void. Hence, the existing and emerging IHRL obligations of Israel to grant citizenship to residents of territory acquired by Israel extend to Palestinians residing in areas of the West Bank illegally annexed by Israel.
The Article argues further that, for the purpose of applying the norms of IHRL that concern the right to citizenship, the definition of annexation extends beyond formal annexation and encompasses de facto annexation as well. Annexation of occupied territory results from the occupier’s display of sovereignty in that territory, among other things, by settling its own population in the occupied territory. In view of the current spread of Israeli settlements across the West Bank, unless Israel removes, within a reasonable time period, many of these settlements, the entire territory of the West Bank may be considered to have been annexed, and the entire Palestinian population of the West Bank would have a strong claim to Israeli citizenship under an emerging norm of international law.
The article also examines the role of international recognition of title to territory in the resolution of the territorial dispute between Israel and the Palestinians. To what extent does international law empower the international community to resolve a territorial dispute over the objection of an affected party, by pronouncing a collective position that reflects near-consensus? The article concludes that a collective recognition by the international community of Palestinian title to territories currently occupied by Israel would have neither a probative value nor a constitutive effect under international law, unless such international position takes the form of U.N. Security Council action in the exercise of its binding powers under Chapter VII of the U.N. Charter.
The article further demonstrates that international law does not support an Israeli claim to sovereignty over the occupied West Bank. This inquiry focuses on a critical examination of a theory recently advanced in legal literature, which predicates such a claim on the doctrine of uti possidetis juris. Finally, the article considers the consequences of the absence of a norm of international law governing the demarcation of the border between Israel and the Palestinians.
The advisory regime would represent a bargain between the Security Council and operating states, which would grant protection for states against the costs that typically attach to non-compliance with the law of war, to the extent that the state followed the legal guidance provided by the international advisors. This article demonstrates that the powers of the Security Council under the U.N. Charter accommodate such a bargain.
The desirability of the proposed advisory regime from a humanitarian perspective, and its appeal for states, depend on the interpretive approach to the law of war that would guide the international advisors. This article identifies an interpretive approach to the law of war that would make the proposed advisory regime the best bargain from a humanitarian perspective that is politically feasible. Such an interpretive approach marks the farthest a state would be willing to stray from the most permissive interpretive approach to the law of war made possible by the indeterminacy of the law to secure the benefits that the advisory regime offers. Use of such an interpretive approach would be secured through the selection of international advisors, tailored to ensure that they are inclined to embrace the desired interpretive approach.
1. When is the threat sufficiently proximate to justify the use of lethal force against the suspected terrorist?
2. Can a state engage in counter-terrorism operations that are likely to result in the unintentional killing of innocent persons?
Far from limiting the reach of universal jurisdiction, the proposed reform would enhance the fight against impunity by diffusing current objections to the exercise of universal jurisdiction in absentia, thereby facilitating the assertion of such jurisdiction by states.
The author argues that international human rights law does not prohibit the repatriation of Israeli settlers. No provision of an international human rights treaty brings the non-repatriation plea of Israeli settlers within the realm of a protected human right. Even if it were possible to point to such a provision, the repatriation of Israeli settlers would probably be permitted under the balancing of interest regime that generally prevails in international human rights law.
The article proceeds to examine the protection granted to illegally implanted settlers under the rules of customary international law that determine the legal consequences of state conduct that violates international law ("State Responsibility Rules"). State Responsibility Rules generally require a state that violated international law to eliminate the consequences of such violation, but the Rules may exempt the violating state from this obligation in view of the interests of individuals. The article shows that examining whether international human rights law prohibits the repatriation of illegally implanted settlers is fundamentally different from examining whether State Responsibility Rules exempt the occupant from carrying out repatriation. The interests of individual settlers may attain sufficient legal significance to support an exemption for an occupant from its duty under State Responsibility Rules to eliminate the consequences of its illegal settlement activity (i.e., the duty to repatriate the settlers) even in the absence of a human rights law prohibition against repatriation. Such an exemption does not depend on a robust balancing-of-interests analysis of the type that prevails in international human rights law. Rather, State Responsibility Rules seem to exempt an occupant from the obligation to repatriate illegally implanted settlers whenever the imposition of such obligation would result in the forcible eviction of a large number of individuals. The author argues that a case for such an exemption has emerged with regard to the settlers implanted by Israel in the occupied Palestinian territories. The article maintains further that the absence of a duty to repatriate the settlers allows for a strong argument in favor of including the interest in non-repatriation within the sphere of interests that Israel may legitimately promote in negotiating the end of occupation.