
Andres Luco
Related Authors
Igor Grossmann
University of Waterloo
Jinhyung Kim
Sogang University
Kevin Tobia
Georgetown University Law Center
Michael Kraus
Yale University
Julian De Freitas
Harvard University
Daniel Bartels
University of Chicago
Brian D . Earp
University of Oxford
Ben Phillips
Arizona State University
Uploads
Papers by Andres Luco
evolutionary explanation of extended benevolence—a human sympathetic capacity
that extends to all nations, races, and even to all sentient beings. This essay draws
on twenty-first century social science to show that Darwin’s explanation is correct
in its broad outlines. Extended benevolence is manifested in institutions such as
legal human rights and democracy, in behaviors such as social movements for
human rights and the protection of nonhuman animals, and in normative attitudes
such as emancipative values and a commitment to promote the rights or welfare of
animals. These phenomena can be substantially explained by cultural evolutionary
forces that trace back to three components of what Darwin called the human “moral
sense”: (1) sympathy, (2) our disposition to follow community rules or norms, and
(3) our capacity to make normative judgments. Extended benevolence likely
emerged with “workarounds,” including political ideologies, that established an
inclusive sympathetic concern for sentient life. It likely became as widespread as it
is now due to recently arisen socio-economic conditions that have created more
opportunities for people to have contact with and take the perspective of a broader
cross-section of humanity, as well as other species.
Against the mere-change view, I shall argue that moral progress does indeed occur, and moreover that it can be understood as increased success in achieving the end of a moral enterprise. The end of a moral enterprise is a state of affairs favored by selection pressures which govern the historical evolution of moral norms. Such an end can be identified through sociological inquiry of the kind that Shermer and others pursue.
evolutionary explanation of extended benevolence—a human sympathetic capacity
that extends to all nations, races, and even to all sentient beings. This essay draws
on twenty-first century social science to show that Darwin’s explanation is correct
in its broad outlines. Extended benevolence is manifested in institutions such as
legal human rights and democracy, in behaviors such as social movements for
human rights and the protection of nonhuman animals, and in normative attitudes
such as emancipative values and a commitment to promote the rights or welfare of
animals. These phenomena can be substantially explained by cultural evolutionary
forces that trace back to three components of what Darwin called the human “moral
sense”: (1) sympathy, (2) our disposition to follow community rules or norms, and
(3) our capacity to make normative judgments. Extended benevolence likely
emerged with “workarounds,” including political ideologies, that established an
inclusive sympathetic concern for sentient life. It likely became as widespread as it
is now due to recently arisen socio-economic conditions that have created more
opportunities for people to have contact with and take the perspective of a broader
cross-section of humanity, as well as other species.
Against the mere-change view, I shall argue that moral progress does indeed occur, and moreover that it can be understood as increased success in achieving the end of a moral enterprise. The end of a moral enterprise is a state of affairs favored by selection pressures which govern the historical evolution of moral norms. Such an end can be identified through sociological inquiry of the kind that Shermer and others pursue.